Voltaire Foundation

for Enlightenment studies

Voltaire’s Russia

Window on the east.

Author: Carolyn H. Wilberger

Volume: 164

Series: SVEC

Publication Date: 1976

ISBN: 978-0-7294-0051-0

Introduction I. France and Russia, 1700-1750 II. Voltaire, historian of Russia: i. The background III. Voltaire, historian of Russia: ii. the concepts IV. Voltaire’s personal contacts with Russia V. Voltaire and Catherine the Great VI. Russia: fact, fiction and formulae VII. The debate: Voltaire versus Rousseau VIII. The debate: philosophes, westernizers and Slavophiles Conclusion Bibliography

Advertisement

Supported by

'If I Were Younger I Would Make Myself Russian': Voltaire's Encounter With the Czars

  • Share full article

By Larry Wolff

  • Nov. 13, 1994

'If I Were Younger I Would Make Myself Russian': Voltaire's Encounter With the Czars

"WHEN, toward the beginning of our century the czar Peter laid the foundations of Petersburg, or rather of his empire," Voltaire observed in the 18th century, "no one foresaw success." No one, he thought, could have imagined that arts and letters would flourish there, that the Russian empire, "almost unknown to us until then, would be civilized in 50 years," and anyone who predicted it would have been dismissed as a visionary. Voltaire spoke for the 18th century's amazement at the phenomenon of Russia, its revolutions and transformations, unforeseeable and unimaginable to those who watched from far away.

Our own century has witnessed revolutions in Russia no less astonishing and unpredictable, right up to the most recent years; tremendous events have left every interested observer, even the visionaries, reeling from the pace at which history has outstripped our imaginations. Voltaire was not altogether unintimidated by the unforeseen success of Russia, of an empire "more vast than all the rest of Europe, than the Roman empire ever was, or that which Alexander conquered from Darius." At the same time, his notion of Russia's volatility allowed him to imagine its success as something precarious, even reversible; he wondered hypothetically if "the most vast empire on earth might relapse into the chaos from which it had only barely emerged." In his trepidation, as in his amazement, Voltaire speaks directly to us across the centuries as we contemplate Russia today, where St. Petersburg has become St. Petersburg again.

"I am older, madame, than the city where you reign," Voltaire wrote to Catherine the Great in 1765, when he was 70 years old. "I even dare to add that I am older than your empire." He dated its rise from the reign of Peter the Great, regarded Russia as the international prodigy of his own lifetime, and therefore as his own titanic contemporary.

Voltaire was born in 1694, and the approaching occasion of his 300th birthday next week will be marked in France, and all over Europe, by an attempt to come to terms with his monumental significance for the 18th century and for ours as well. Voltaire's own vast empire of plays, fables, letters, histories, poems and polemics made him, too, a power to be contemplated with awe and amazement. One still catches one's breath at the dazzling irreverence of the "Philosophical Dictionary," in which he alphabetically, blasphemously, comically revised anything and everything -- from atheism, baptism and circumcision to torture, transubstantiation and virtue.

What made him the first modern intellectual was his refusal to recognize any subject as off-limits, his readiness to write about whatever excited his anger or admiration, his contempt or curiosity. He was also the first of many modern intellectuals to take Russia as his subject -- "almost unknown to us until then," he wrote -- to make of it a lifelong fascination and to demand that his contemporaries recognize its overwhelming importance. Voltaire was a child when Peter built his fleet, traveled incognito to Holland and England to learn about the world outside Russia and began to build the city of St. Petersburg on the marshes by the Gulf of Finland. Voltaire was a young man in 1717, when Peter's visit to Paris created the kind of sensation that other Russian leaders have also excited, even in our own times, in going abroad.

"Neither he nor I suspected that one day I would be his historian," Voltaire remarked later, making his encounter with Russia a matter of literary destiny.

Actually he had other matters on his mind in 1717. A week after Peter was welcomed to Paris by the 7-year-old King of France, Louis XV, Voltaire was arrested and imprisoned in the Bastille under suspicion of spreading satirical, even salacious, witticisms about members of the French royal family. He went into prison as Francois-Marie Arouet, emerged a year later with the new name Voltaire, and immediately proceeded to make it famous with the tragedy of "Oedipus," performed at the Comedie Francaise in 1718. He did not take up the subject of Russia until the 1730's, the decade that made him the most celebrated philosopher in Europe and the foremost figure of the Enlightenment. In his "Philosophical Letters," about England, and his "Elements of the Philosophy of Newton" he rallied his readers to the values of political liberty, religious toleration and empirical science, not to mention the good sense of inoculation against smallpox.

Voltaire began to write about Russia in a best-selling book about the recent rise and fall of empires, the "History of Charles XII," first published in 1731, and avidly consumed by 18th-century readers in edition after edition. It was the story of the Swedish warrior King who, at the beginning of the century, had sought to create an enormous empire by military conquest. Russia was the most formidable object of the King's campaigns, and Voltaire's account became the 18th century's introduction to the unfamiliar Russian landscape in all its modern geopolitical significance. In 1812, when the armies of France invaded Russia, Napoleon was brooding over the story of Charles XII, as told by Voltaire, a story that posed the challenge of the ultimate imperial prize.

In the "Philosophical Letters" Voltaire boldly proclaimed that the greatest man of the ages was neither Caesar nor Alexander but Sir Isaac Newton, for conquerors were nothing but "illustrious criminals." Yet Charles XII of Sweden was just such a conqueror, pursuing an apparently unlimited ambition until he was finally defeated by Peter the Great at the battle of Poltava in 1709. Voltaire would claim that he recorded the history of Charles so that kings might be "cured of the folly of conquests," but the great appeal of his book to the public was as an epic tale of military adventures set in a land that was until Peter's time "scarcely known to Europe." In that phrase Voltaire summed up the central paradox of Russia, for if Russia could be unknown to Europe, then it was in some sense emphatically distinct from Europe. "The Muscovites were less civilized than the Mexicans when they were discovered by Cortes," he reflected. "They were stagnating in ignorance, in the absence of all the arts."

VOLTAIRE'S invocation of Cortes revealed a vision of Russia as the New World of the 18th century, hovering on the horizon of the literary imagination, awaiting a dual discovery by the conqueror's sword and the philosopher's pen. Even as Voltaire let his readers revel in the adventures of the warrior King, Charles XII, it was really the writer, Voltaire himself, who consummated the work of discovery by putting the picture of Russia before the public of Paris, by making an irresistibly readable map that guaranteed that Russia would never be unknown to Europe again.

He also provided an invaluable key for reading that map. What was crucial was the notion of a comparative scale -- from less civilized to more civilized -- which added a new dimension to the map of the world. Each land possessed not only a set of geographical coordinates but also a rank in the scale of civilization. In the 1740's, Voltaire began to work on a universal history, published as the "Essay on Manners" in 1756, charting the customs of nations around the globe from China to Constantinople to Canterbury, beginning with the reign of Charlemagne. The account of Russia was a bloody comedy of false Dmitris -- "all these adventures" which seem so fabulous, and could not occur "among civilized peoples who have some form of regular government." As for Russian manners, Voltaire described a world without beds, in which people slept on planks, with perhaps the crude comfort of animal skins.

Yet what made Russia so interesting to Voltaire for his grand scheme of universal manners was not that Russia was once so much "less civilized" than other lands, but rather that in Voltaire's own lifetime it was apparently becoming "more civilized" at an astonishing pace. The model of a world made up of more and less civilized lands was not simply static; it was capable of dynamic adjustments, advances and accelerations. "Thirty centuries could not have accomplished what Peter did when he traveled for several years," wrote Voltaire, and this tribute to Peter's educational travels was really an appreciation of the lands that he visited, where he learned so much.

In the inspirational conclusion to the "Essay on Manners" Voltaire saluted the wealth and wisdom of Europe as a whole, "from Petersburg to Madrid," but he declared that there must be some special genius in the character of "our part of Europe." Thus he planted his flag, and proudly claimed for himself and his readers a privileged corner of the Continent.

The word "civilization" was just coming into use in the 18th century, in French and in English, and conservative men of letters preferred to avoid it as a newfangled neologism. Samuel Johnson would not include it in his dictionary, insisting that it was only a legal term for the process by which a criminal matter became a civil one, i.e., civilization. The younger generation, in the person of James Boswell, dared to differ with Johnson: "He would not admit civilization, but only civility. With great deference to him, I thought civilization, from to civilize, better in the sense opposed to barbarity."

Voltaire, in French, also shied away from the new abstract noun, though no one did more to invest the word with its unprecedented rhetorical powers than the man who both proposed and personified the genius of "our part of Europe." If civilization was difficult to define with precision, it was also an irresistible idea, encouraging a sense of categorical confidence in superior achievement, from the ministries of government and economy to the academies of arts and sciences.

Voltaire called on his contemporaries to recognize that the civilizing of Russia was the great event of their century. They harkened to him because the image of Russia becoming civilized offered an inspirational validation of their own values and institutions. We have allowed ourselves some of the same satisfying sense of self-justification now in the 1990's, as we applaud from a distance the adoption of our own political and economic values in Russia.

Voltaire's excitement about Russia becoming civilized in the 18th century found its echo across the centuries on the front page of The New York Times in August 1991; beneath the headline "After the Coup: Old Guard's Last Gasp," the correspondent in Moscow found Russian reformers finally ready "for the mammoth task of civilizing their country." Voltaire's vision of Russia on the verge of civilization was so persuasive in its own time that the formula found a life of its own, and Russia appears to us forever on the verge.

VOLTAIRE himself seemed to remain for decades on the verge of a voyage to Russia, a voyage passionately contemplated, but never accomplished. Indeed, for one whose worldly interests ranged around the globe he rarely departed from "our part of Europe," encompassing France, England, Holland, Switzerland and the German states. In the 1730's and 40's, while his fame traveled all over Europe, he himself kept returning to the chateau of Cirey in Champagne, where he lived with the great love of his life, the Marquise du Chatelet. Voltaire adored her for her intellectual brilliance in science and mathematics.

"The Marquise du Chatelet did me the honor of reading Descartes's 'Dioptrics' with me several days ago," he wrote in a letter from Cirey. "We both admired the proportion that he says he found between the sine of the angle of incidence and the sine of the angle of refraction."

In 1740, he was writing his sensational play "Mahomet," dramatizing the evils of religious fanaticism, concealing his criticism of Christianity within an Islamic mise en scene, but he nevertheless declined an invitation from an English friend to visit the Muslim city of Constantinople.

"I would pass some months at Constantinople with you, if I could live without that lady; whom I look as a great man," he wrote, paying tribute in awkward English to the marquise. "She understands Newton, she despises superstition, in short she makes me happy." The gravity of Newtonian romance was the obstacle and the excuse that kept him from making this particular voyage to the east.

When the Marquise du Chatelet died after childbirth in 1749 (the child was not Voltaire's), he visited the court of Frederick the Great in Berlin; that was as far east as he ever traveled and the closest he ever came to Russia. In the 1750's he retired to Ferney, on the border between France and Switzerland, where an irreverent writer, who sometimes appeared subversive, could find refuge from the law on one side of the border or the other. There he remained for the last 20 years of his life, not even returning to Paris until the year of his death in 1778.

It was in Ferney that he passionately contemplated Russia, completed his "History of the Russian Empire Under Peter the Great" and conducted an extraordinary personal correspondence with Catherine the Great in St. Petersburg. He also thought again and again about going to Russia, but never made the voyage.

He eagerly accepted an invitation from Russia to write the biography of Peter, but declined to go study the subject in St. Petersburg. Instead, big batches of documents were shipped across the Continent to him. Writing about Russia from a distance, he preferred not to look too closely at some of the awkward episodes in Peter's life, for the book was conceived as a monument to Peter's achievement in civilizing Russia. For instance, the author of "Oedipus" was troubled by the weight of historical opinion that held Peter responsible for the death of his own son.

"The sad end of the czarevitch embarrasses me a little," Voltaire privately remarked, but he publicly justified his hero on the grounds that civilization itself was at stake, that the czarevitch wanted to undo his father's work in Russia, "to plunge it again into darkness." Voltaire's tribute to Peter was so uncritical as to encourage rumors that the author had been corrupted by Russian gifts of fancy furs.

RUSSIA itself, however, appeared in the books as rough and alien terrain, the better to highlight the heroism of the Czar. "My purpose is to show what the czar Peter created," wrote Voltaire, "rather than to unscramble uselessly the ancient chaos." His legend of Peter was almost biblical in its proportions, the history of creation out of chaos and darkness, with an ominous warning that this work of genesis could come undone.

Voltaire began by asking his readers to take map in hand to follow him on an armchair tour of Russia, through a geographical description that became virtually definitive for the 18th century when its chief passages were plagiarized and reprinted in the great 18th-century "Encyclopedia."

The tour was deeply disorienting on account of its enormous range, its encounters with primitive peoples and its posing of a peculiar geographical puzzle. "If, after having looked over all these vast provinces, you cast your eye to the east," wrote Voltaire to his adventurous readers, "it is there that the limits of Europe and Asia are still confused." It would be impossible to say precisely where one might be, because "one doesn't know anymore where Europe finishes and where Asia commences." This declaration of continental confusion was, in fact, an accurate account of the state of 18th-century geography, for the border between Europe and Asia -- though all agreed that it had to cut across Russia somewhere -- was a subject of controversy. Our own cartographical convention, that the Ural Mountains mark the border, had only just been proposed in the 18th century as one solution among several, and the maps of the period offered a variety of alternative borders, some beginning at the Don River and some farther east, at the Volga.

VOLTAIRE seized on the significance of this confusion, the impossibility of sorting out the balance between Europe and Asia when casting one's eye over the transcontinental expanse of the Russian empire. Indeed, he highlighted the Oriental aspect of Russia, the more dramatically to emphasize the effort of Peter in making Russia a part of Europe. Voltaire believed that Russia's allegiance to Europe was as precious and as precarious as its ascent toward civilization. He reminded his readers that Peter had done them the honor of looking for inspiration to "our part of Europe," and that he had consciously chosen "to introduce into his estates neither Turkish nor Persian manners, but ours." The transformation of Russia was also the ultimate vindication of Europe.

In this matter Voltaire stood at the center of an 18th-century controversy that demanded attention from the biggest names in the biggest books. Montesquieu, in "The Spirit of the Laws," located Russia in Europe, and was consequently less impressed by Peter's achievement "in giving the manners and customs of Europe to a European nation."

Rousseau, on the other hand, in "The Social Contract," refused to admire Peter's campaign to give his subjects the manners and customs of Europe: "He tried to turn them into Germans or Englishmen instead of making them Russians." Voltaire was far more deeply occupied with Russia than either Montesquieu or Rousseau, urgently concerned with comprehending the relation of Russia to Europe as a whole, dedicated to the proposition that making Russia a part of Europe was worth tremendous efforts of statesmen and intellectuals alike.

Two centuries before Charles de Gaulle raised the slogan "Europe From the Atlantic to the Urals," Voltaire declared his own allegiance, at a time when the Urals possessed little incantatory significance and the study of Russia still posed the question of where Europe finishes and Asia commences.

In 1762 Catherine came to the throne of Russia in a neatly executed army coup, deposing her husband, Peter's grandson, and allegedly having him killed. She soon received in St. Petersburg, posted from an estate on the border between France and Switzerland, a copy of Voltaire's book about Peter, and she wrote back more than politely to thank the author.

It turned out, as she told him, that ever since coming to Russia as a teen-age princess from Germany almost 20 years before, she had been an enthusiastic reader and admirer of Voltaire. They now began a long correspondence of mutual admiration, sometimes even outrageous flattery, between Ferney and St. Petersburg, without ever coming face to face.

Catherine's side of the correspondence has often been interpreted as a public relations move to advertise her reign in the best possible light before the enlightened public abroad; this interpretation appeared more plausible in the 20th century when the Government of the Soviet Union paid similar attention to the good will of sympathetic foreign intellectuals. Voltaire's side of the correspondence has been interpreted more critically still, as evidence of an aging philosopher's hopeless susceptibility to kind words from crowned heads.

Yet to comprehend Voltaire's strangely extravagant correspondence with Catherine means seeing it as the stupendous climax of a lifelong fascination with Russia, one that was never without some elements of heartfelt fantasy and starry-eyed delusion.

Our image of Voltaire, indeed our historical interpretation of the whole Enlightenment, has been powerfully revised over the last generation by the historian Peter Gay, who argued that Voltaire was no abstract philosopher but an intellectual realistically engaged with the urgent social and political issues of his century.

In the case of Russia, however, "where the limits of Europe and Asia are still confused," Voltaire found himself writing at the limits of urgent realism and confused fantasy, and his profound insight into Russia's contemporary importance stimulated his vivid imagination to enhance a remote perspective. Voltaire's Russia bore some relation to the invented worlds of the famous parables, like Zadig's Babylon or Candide's El Dorado, and when he wrote to Catherine to congratulate her on her legislative efforts, he made Russia into the mythological empire of the Enlightenment: "I would not have guessed in 1700 that Reason, one day, would come to Moscow, at the voice of a princess born in Germany, and that she would assemble in a great hall idolaters, Moslems, Greeks, Latins, Lutherans, who would all become her children." His mounting outrage against the "infamy" of religious fanaticism in France conditioned his fanciful parable of ecumenical harmony in Russia.

Voltaire celebrated Catherine for demonstrating her commitment to modern medicine by permitting herself to be inoculated against smallpox. She returned the compliment by insisting that the best medicine for her, recovering from inoculation, was the laughter that came with reading "Candide." The happy ending of "Candide" brought its whole cast of long-suffering characters together in Turkey, to cultivate their garden, and the philosopher's fable found its place in the Czarina's imperial policy when Catherine went to war against the Ottoman empire in 1768; she playfully promised to conquer Constantinople on Voltaire's behalf, so that he, too, might retire in Turkey, just like Candide.

In a strange spirit of exhilaration Voltaire rooted for the Russian armies on the frontiers of Europe, just as he had once relished the military adventures of Charles XII on the same terrain. "I expect very humbly of destiny and of your genius," he wrote, "the unscrambling of all this chaos in which the earth is plunged, from Danzig to the mouth of the Danube." Voltaire made a mental division of the Continent into western Europe and eastern Europe, defined the limits of chaos, and then cheered for the advent of Catherine's "genius" in the Crimea, in Moldavia, in Poland and in Bulgaria.

IN his letters he imagined that he, too, was traveling in spirit, "to the Dardanelles, to the Danube, to the Black Sea, to Bender, into the Crimea and especially to St. Petersburg." His fantasy proposed a magic arrow, to carry him across the Continent: "If I had that arrow I would be in Petersburg today, instead of stupidly presenting, from the foot of the Alps, my profound respect and inviolable attachment to the sovereign of Azov, of Caffa and of my heart."

The misplaced jingoism of the old philosopher found inspiration in a peculiar poetry, the poetry of geographical place names. His map of Europe was suddenly illuminated, and behold, it was marked with rivers, seas, peninsulas and cities of unsuspected significance, far from the foot of the Alps. As he gazed across Europe toward Russia, he was both thrilled and alarmed to discover the unfamiliar expanse of a continent he thought he already knew.

"Everybody who can possibly do so should go to Russia," George Bernard Shaw wrote in 1931, when he himself had just returned, much impressed. The phenomenon of famous foreign visitors to the Soviet Union in the 20th century has been a history of unusual infatuation, unexpected disillusionments and unexpressed reservations. Sidney and Beatrice Webb, Shaw's fellow Fabians, made the voyage in 1932, and wrote a book that took its title -- "Soviet Communism: A New Civilization?" -- right out of the lexicography of the Enlightenment. American artists and writers who traveled to Russia, like Paul Robeson and Lillian Hellman, were later called to account in the witch hunts of the 1950's. As for French intellectuals, through the 1960's the intimidating team of Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir returned to Russia repeatedly.

Two hundred years earlier Voltaire hesitated and equivocated. "I will be, truly, 70 years old, and I do not have the vigor of a Turk," he wrote to Catherine. "If I should die on the road, I will put on my little tomb: Here lies the admirer of the august Catherine." He was thinking about a French philosopher of the previous century, Descartes, who traveled to Sweden to tutor Queen Christina; he caught pneumonia there and died.

Voltaire was to die in Paris in 1778, not St. Petersburg, but he lived long enough to see another celebrity of the Enlightenment, Diderot, the editor of the "Encyclopedia," cause a sensation by making the journey to Russia in 1773. "All my life I will congratulate myself on the voyage to Petersburg," Diderot wrote afterward to Catherine, and Voltaire at Ferney was jealous. He was bitter at the thought of another French philosopher at Catherine's court, but above all he resented the simple reality of the Diderot voyage, which shattered his own overwhelming sense of Russia's mythological remoteness.

Voltaire stayed home and cultivated his garden, and Catherine encouraged him with the news that she was cultivating hers at the same time, in a parallel universe: "You are seeding at Ferney; I am doing the same this spring at Tsarskoye Selo. This name will seem to you perhaps a little hard to pronounce; however, it is a place that I find delicious because I am planting and seeding there. The Baroness of Thunder-ten-Tronckh found her palace quite the most beautiful of all possible palaces." Catherine played to his pleasure in the alien names of places in Russia, while transforming herself into a character from "Candide." Voltaire and Catherine encountered each other in the fantasy space created in correspondence, where he could sign himself to her, "your old Russian of Ferney."

"If I were younger I would make myself Russian," he declared to Catherine, who really had made herself Russian at a young age. In fact Voltaire did once become Russian, very briefly, for the duration of a poem, written in 1760. The poem was called "The Russian in Paris," and Voltaire, always a man of many pseudonyms, invented the persona of a Russian diplomat, Ivan Alethof, as the supposed poet. The verse took the form of a dialogue between two characters, a Parisian and a Russian. The latter humbly presents himself as in need of tutelage from the French: "I come to enlighten myself, to be instructed among you / To see a famous people, to observe them and to listen." The Parisian, however, sends him on his way, dubiously posing the rhetorical question: "On the shores of the Occident what can you learn?"

It was Voltaire, more than anyone, who created an 18th-century image of Russia emerging from chaos, darkness and barbarism, Russia conceived from the vantage point of "our part of Europe." Yet he was also capable of assuming the identity of a Russian in Paris, and deploying the Russian perspective to mock at French presumption, including his own. Voltaire was born in Paris in 1694, and his Parisian origin defined his perspective on Petersburg. Yet after looking hard at Russia for decade after decade, he saw the Occident in a different light as well.

Three hundred years after his birth, the same question -- "On the shores of the Occident what can you learn?" -- echoes for us, in our relations with Russia, with an undeniable but ambivalent significance. Voltaire played both parts in the dialogue of "The Russian in Paris," because he participated in the triumphant cultural confidence of what his contemporaries were beginning to call "civilization," and because he also made it his vocation as an intellectual to excoriate them for their own infamies and inadequacies.

There is a conventional wisdom about Russia that tends to emphasize an unchanging historical character, and to find dark continuities even in the revolutionary leap from the empire of the Romanov czars to that of the Soviet commissars. It is perhaps more difficult for us to discern the ways in which foreigners help to create the appearance of continuities by applying the same familiar formulas to what they see in Russia, from regime to regime and across the centuries. Tolstoy made the point with irony in "War and Peace" when he created the character of Napoleon, who gazed upon Moscow and resolved to teach the Russians "the meaning of true civilization."

Today, when Russia is again in the throes of revolutionary transformation, when the ultimate direction of revolution is uncertain, when we have every reason to feel an urgent investment in the outcome, we can find in Voltaire a warning against indifference and a challenge to renew our perspective. He offers us a sort of philosophical dictionary of the whole range of intellectual responses to Russia -- from arrogance and ambivalence to vicariousness and vindication -- that have been adopted and adapted ever since the 18th century. His philosophical calculation of Russia's geographical remove enabled him to study it from afar, and with a paradoxical sense of alien intimacy, which he has bequeathed to us.

Explore More in Books

Want to know about the best books to read and the latest news start here..

The complicated, generous life  of Paul Auster, who died on April 30 , yielded a body of work of staggering scope and variety .

“Real Americans,” a new novel by Rachel Khong , follows three generations of Chinese Americans as they all fight for self-determination in their own way .

“The Chocolate War,” published 50 years ago, became one of the most challenged books in the United States. Its author, Robert Cormier, spent years fighting attempts to ban it .

Joan Didion’s distinctive prose and sharp eye were tuned to an outsider’s frequency, telling us about ourselves in essays that are almost reflexively skeptical. Here are her essential works .

Each week, top authors and critics join the Book Review’s podcast to talk about the latest news in the literary world. Listen here .

  • CC0 version of this metadata

Voltaire's Russia

Email this record.

Please enter the email address that the record information will be sent to.

Please add any additional information to be included within the email.

Cite this record

Chicago style, bibliographic details, item description, terms of use, views and downloads.

If you are the owner of this record, you can report an update to it here: Report update to this record

Report an update

We require your email address in order to let you know the outcome of your enquiry.

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

François-Marie d’Arouet (1694–1778), better known by his pen name Voltaire, was a French writer and public activist who played a singular role in defining the eighteenth-century movement called the Enlightenment. At the center of his work was a new conception of philosophy and the philosopher that in several crucial respects influenced the modern concept of each. Yet in other ways Voltaire was not a philosopher at all in the modern sense of the term. He wrote as many plays, stories, and poems as patently philosophical tracts, and he in fact directed many of his critical writings against the philosophical pretensions of recognized philosophers such as Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes. He was, however, a vigorous defender of a conception of natural science that served in his mind as the antidote to vain and fruitless philosophical investigation. In clarifying this new distinction between science and philosophy, and especially in fighting vigorously for it in public campaigns directed against the perceived enemies of fanaticism and superstition, Voltaire pointed modern philosophy down several paths that it subsequently followed.

To capture Voltaire’s unconventional place in the history of philosophy, this article will be structured in a particular way. First, a full account of Voltaire’s life is offered, not merely as background context for his philosophical work, but as an argument about the way that his particular career produced his particular contributions to European philosophy. Second, a survey of Voltaire’s philosophical views is offered so as to attach the legacy of what Voltaire did with the intellectual viewpoints that his activities reinforced.

1.1 Voltaire’s Early Years (1694–1726)

1.2 the english period (1726–1729), 1.3 becoming a philosophe, 1.4 the newton wars (1732–1745), 1.5 from french newtonian to enlightenment philosophe (1745–1755), 1.6 fighting for philosophie (1755–1778), 1.7 voltaire, philosophe icon of enlightenment philosophie (1778–present), 2.1 liberty, 2.2 hedonism, 2.3 skepticism, 2.4 newtonian empirical science, 2.5 toward science without metaphysics, primary literature, primary literature in translation, secondary literature, other internet resources, related entries, 1. voltaire’s life: the philosopher as critic and public activist.

Voltaire only began to identify himself with philosophy and the philosophe identity during middle age. His work Lettres philosophiques , published in 1734 when he was forty years old, was the key turning point in this transformation. Before this date, Voltaire’s life in no way pointed him toward the philosophical destiny that he was later to assume. His early orientation toward literature and libertine sociability, however, shaped his philosophical identity in crucial ways.

François-Marie d’Arouet was born in 1694, the fourth of five children, to a well-to-do public official and his well bred aristocratic wife. In its fusion of traditional French aristocratic pedigree with the new wealth and power of royal bureaucratic administration, the d’Arouet family was representative of elite society in France during the reign of Louis XIV. The young François-Marie acquired from his parents the benefits of prosperity and political favor, and from the Jesuits at the prestigious Collège Louis-le-Grand in Paris he also acquired a first-class education. François-Marie also acquired an introduction to modern letters from his father who was active in the literary culture of the period both in Paris and at the royal court of Versailles. François senior appears to have enjoyed the company of men of letters, yet his frustration with his son’s ambition to become a writer is notorious. From early in his youth, Voltaire aspired to emulate his idols Molière, Racine, and Corneille and become a playwright, yet Voltaire’s father strenuously opposed the idea, hoping to install his son instead in a position of public authority. First as a law student, then as a lawyer’s apprentice, and finally as a secretary to a French diplomat, Voltaire attempted to fulfill his father’s wishes. But in each case, he ended up abandoning his posts, sometimes amidst scandal.

Escaping from the burdens of these public obligations, Voltaire would retreat into the libertine sociability of Paris. It was here in the 1720s, during the culturally vibrant period of the Regency government between the reigns of Louis XIV and XV (1715–1723), that Voltaire established one dimension of his identity. His wit and congeniality were legendary even as a youth, so he had few difficulties establishing himself as a popular figure in Regency literary circles. He also learned how to play the patronage game so important to those with writerly ambitions. Thanks, therefore, to some artfully composed writings, a couple of well-made contacts, more than a few bon mots , and a little successful investing, especially during John Law’s Mississippi Bubble fiasco, Voltaire was able to establish himself as an independent man of letters in Paris. His literary debut occurred in 1718 with the publication of his Oedipe , a reworking of the ancient tragedy that evoked the French classicism of Racine and Corneille. The play was first performed at the home of the Duchesse du Maine at Sceaux, a sign of Voltaire’s quick ascent to the very pinnacle of elite literary society. Its published title page also announced the new pen name that Voltaire would ever after deploy.

During the Regency, Voltaire circulated widely in elite circles such as those that congregated at Sceaux, but he also cultivated more illicit and libertine sociability as well. This pairing was not at all uncommon during this time, and Voltaire’s intellectual work in the 1720s—a mix of poems and plays that shifted between playful libertinism and serious classicism seemingly without pause—illustrated perfectly the values of pleasure, honnêteté , and good taste that were the watchwords of this cultural milieu. Philosophy was also a part of this mix, and during the Regency the young Voltaire was especially shaped by his contacts with the English aristocrat, freethinker,and Jacobite Lord Bolingbroke. Bolingbroke lived in exile in France during the Regency period, and Voltaire was a frequent visitor to La Source, the Englishman’s estate near Orléans. The chateau served as a reunion point for a wide range of intellectuals, and many believe that Voltaire was first introduced to natural philosophy generally, and to the work of Locke and the English Newtonians specifically, at Bolingbroke’s estate. It was certainly true that these ideas, especially in their more deistic and libertine configurations, were at the heart of Bolingbroke’s identity.

Yet even if Voltaire was introduced to English philosophy in this way, its influence on his thought was most shaped by his brief exile in England between 1726–29. The occasion for his departure was an affair of honor. A very powerful aristocrat, the Duc de Rohan, accused Voltaire of defamation, and in the face of this charge the untitled writer chose to save face and avoid more serious prosecution by leaving the country indefinitely. In the spring of 1726, therefore, Voltaire left Paris for England.

It was during his English period that Voltaire’s transition into his mature philosophe identity began. Bolingbroke, whose address Voltaire left in Paris as his own forwarding address, was one conduit of influence. In particular, Voltaire met through Bolingbroke Jonathan Swift, Alexander Pope, and John Gay, writers who were at that moment beginning to experiment with the use of literary forms such as the novel and theater in the creation of a new kind of critical public politics. Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels , which appeared only months before Voltaire’s arrival, is the most famous exemplar of this new fusion of writing with political criticism. Later the same year Bolingbroke also brought out the first issue of the Craftsman , a political journal that served as the public platform for his circle’s Tory opposition to the Whig oligarchy in England. The Craftsman helped to create English political journalism in the grand style, and for the next three years Voltaire moved in Bolingbroke’s circle, absorbing the culture and sharing in the public political contestation that was percolating all around him.

Voltaire did not restrict himself to Bolingbroke’s circle alone, however. After Bolingbroke, his primary contact in England was a merchant by the name of Everard Fawkener. Fawkener introduced Voltaire to a side of London life entirely different from that offered by Bolingbroke’s circle of Tory intellectuals. This included the Whig circles that Bolingbroke’s group opposed. It also included figures such as Samuel Clarke and other self-proclaimed Newtonians. Voltaire did not meet Newton himself before Sir Isaac’s death in March, 1727, but he did meet his sister—learning from her the famous myth of Newton’s apple, which Voltaire would play a major role in making famous. Voltaire also came to know the other Newtonians in Clarke’s circle, and since he became proficient enough with English to write letters and even fiction in the language, it is very likely that he immersed himself in their writings as well. Voltaire also visited Holland during these years, forming important contacts with Dutch journalists and publishers and meeting Willem’s Gravesande and other Dutch Newtonian savants. Given his other activities, it is also likely that Voltaire frequented the coffeehouses of London even if no firm evidence survives confirming that he did. It would not be surprising, therefore, to learn that Voltaire attended the Newtonian public lectures of John Theophilus Desaguliers or those of one of his rivals. Whatever the precise conduits, all of his encounters in England made Voltaire into a very knowledgeable student of English natural philosophy.

When French officials granted Voltaire permission to re-enter Paris in 1729, he was devoid of pensions and banned from the royal court at Versailles. But he was also a different kind of writer and thinker. It is no doubt overly grandiose to say with Lord Morley that, “Voltaire left France a poet and returned to it a sage.” It is also an exaggeration to say that he was transformed from a poet into a philosophe while in England. For one, these two sides of Voltaire’s intellectual identity were forever intertwined, and he never experienced an absolute transformation from one into the other at any point in his life. But the English years did trigger a transformation in him.

After his return to France, Voltaire worked hard to restore his sources of financial and political support. The financial problems were the easiest to solve. In 1729, the French government staged a sort of lottery to help amortize some of the royal debt. A friend perceived an opportunity for investors in the structure of the government’s offering, and at a dinner attended by Voltaire he formed a society to purchase shares. Voltaire participated, and in the fall of that year when the returns were posted he had made a fortune. Voltaire’s inheritance from his father also became available to him at the same time, and from this date forward Voltaire never again struggled financially. This result was no insignificant development since Voltaire’s financial independence effectively freed him from one dimension of the patronage system so necessary to aspiring writers and intellectuals in the period. In particular, while other writers were required to appeal to powerful financial patrons in order to secure the livelihood that made possible their intellectual careers, Voltaire was never again beholden to these imperatives.

The patronage structures of Old Regime France provided more than economic support to writers, however, and restoring the crédit upon which his reputation as a writer and thinker depended was far less simple. Gradually, however, through a combination of artfully written plays, poems, and essays and careful self-presentation in Parisian society, Voltaire began to regain his public stature. In the fall of 1732, when the next stage in his career began to unfold, Voltaire was residing at the royal court of Versailles, a sign that his re-establishment in French society was all but complete.

During this rehabilitation, Voltaire also formed a new relationship that was to prove profoundly influential in the subsequent decades. He became reacquainted with Emilie Le Tonnier de Breteuil,the daughter of one of his earliest patrons, who married in 1722 to become the Marquise du Châtelet. Emilie du Châtelet was twenty-nine years old in the spring of 1733 when Voltaire began his relationship with her. She was also a uniquely accomplished woman. Du Châtelet’s father, the Baron de Breteuil, hosted a regular gathering of men of letters that included Voltaire, and his daughter, ten years younger than Voltaire, shared in these associations. Her father also ensured that Emilie received an education that was exceptional for girls at the time. She studied Greek and Latin and trained in mathematics, and when Voltaire reconnected with her in 1733 she was a very knowledgeable thinker in her own right even if her own intellectual career, which would include an original treatise in natural philosophy and a complete French translation of Newton’s Principia Mathematica —still the only complete French translation ever published—had not yet begun. Her intellectual talents combined with her vivacious personality drew Voltaire to her, and although Du Châtelet was a titled aristocrat married to an important military officer, the couple was able to form a lasting partnership that did not interfere with Du Châtelet’s marriage. This arrangement proved especially beneficial to Voltaire when scandal forced him to flee Paris and to establish himself permanently at the Du Châtelet family estate at Cirey. From 1734, when this arrangement began, to 1749, when Du Châtelet died during childbirth, Cirey was the home to each along with the site of an intense intellectual collaboration. It was during this period that both Voltaire and Du Châtelet became widely known philosophical figures, and the intellectual history of each before 1749 is most accurately described as the history of the couple’s joint intellectual endeavors.

For Voltaire, the events that sent him fleeing to Cirey were also the impetus for much of his work while there. While in England, Voltaire had begun to compose a set of letters framed according to the well-established genre of a traveler reporting to friends back home about foreign lands. Montesquieu’s 1721 Lettres Persanes , which offered a set of fictionalized letters by Persians allegedly traveling in France, and Swift’s 1726 Gulliver’s Travels were clear influences when Voltaire conceived his work. But unlike the authors of these overtly fictionalized accounts, Voltaire innovated by adopting a journalistic stance instead, one that offered readers an empirically recognizable account of several aspects of English society. Originally titled Letters on England , Voltaire left a draft of the text with a London publisher before returning home in 1729. Once in France, he began to expand the work, adding to the letters drafted while in England, which focused largely on the different religious sects of England and the English Parliament, several new letters including some on English philosophy. The new text, which included letters on Bacon, Locke, Newton and the details of Newtonian natural philosophy along with an account of the English practice of inoculation for smallpox, also acquired a new title when it was first published in France in 1734: Lettres philosophiques .

Before it appeared, Voltaire attempted to get official permission for the book from the royal censors, a requirement in France at the time. His publisher, however, ultimately released the book without these approvals and without Voltaire’s permission. This made the first edition of the Lettres philosophiques illicit, a fact that contributed to the scandal that it triggered, but one that in no way explains the furor the book caused. Historians in fact still scratch their heads when trying to understand why Voltaire’s Lettres philosophiques proved to be so controversial. The only thing that is clear is that the work did cause a sensation that subsequently triggered a rapid and overwhelming response on the part of the French authorities. The book was publicly burned by the royal hangman several months after its release, and this act turned Voltaire into a widely known intellectual outlaw. Had it been executed, a royal lettre de cachet would have sent Voltaire to the royal prison of the Bastille as a result of his authorship of Lettres philosophiques ; instead, he was able to flee with Du Châtelet to Cirey where the couple used the sovereignty granted by her aristocratic title to create a safe haven and base for Voltaire’s new position as a philosophical rebel and writer in exile.

Had Voltaire been able to avoid the scandal triggered by the Lettres philosophiques , it is highly likely that he would have chosen to do so. Yet once it was thrust upon him, he adopted the identity of the philosophical exile and outlaw writer with conviction, using it to create a new identity for himself, one that was to have far reaching consequences for the history of Western philosophy. At first, Newtonian science served as the vehicle for this transformation. In the decades before 1734, a series of controversies had erupted, especially in France, about the character and legitimacy of Newtonian science, especially the theory of universal gravitation and the physics of gravitational attraction through empty space. Voltaire positioned his Lettres philosophiques as an intervention into these controversies, drafting a famous and widely cited letter that used an opposition between Newton and Descartes to frame a set of fundamental differences between English and French philosophy at the time. He also included other letters about Newtonian science in the work while linking (or so he claimed) the philosophies of Bacon, Locke, and Newton into an English philosophical complex that he championed as a remedy for the perceived errors and illusions perpetuated on the French by René Descartes and Nicolas Malebranche. Voltaire did not invent this framework, but he did use it to enflame a set of debates that were then raging, debates that placed him and a small group of young members of the Royal Academy of Sciences in Paris into apparent opposition to the older and more established members of this bastion of official French science. Once installed at Cirey, both Voltaire and Du Châtelet further exploited this apparent division by engaging in a campaign on behalf of Newtonianism, one that continually targeted an imagined monolith called French Academic Cartesianism as the enemy against which they in the name of Newtonianism were fighting.

The centerpiece of this campaign was Voltaire’s Éléments de la Philosophie de Newton , which was first published in 1738 and then again in 1745 in a new and definitive edition that included a new section, first published in 1740, devoted to Newton’s metaphysics. Voltaire offered this book as a clear, accurate, and accessible account of Newton’s philosophy suitable for ignorant Frenchman (a group that he imagined to be large). But he also conceived of it as a machine de guerre directed against the Cartesian establishment, which he believed was holding France back from the modern light of scientific truth. Vociferous criticism of Voltaire and his work quickly erupted, with some critics emphasizing his rebellious and immoral proclivities while others focused on his precise scientific views. Voltaire collapsed both challenges into a singular vision of his enemy as “backward Cartesianism”. As he fought fiercely to defend his positions, an unprecedented culture war erupted in France centered on the character and value of Newtonian natural philosophy. Du Châtelet contributed to this campaign by writing a celebratory review of Voltaire’s Éléments in the Journal des savants , the most authoritative French learned periodical of the day. The couple also added to their scientific credibility by receiving separate honorable mentions in the 1738 Paris Academy prize contest on the nature of fire. Voltaire likewise worked tirelessly rebutting critics and advancing his positions in pamphlets and contributions to learned periodicals. By 1745, when the definitive edition of Voltaire’s Éléments was published, the tides of thought were turning his way, and by 1750 the perception had become widespread that France had been converted from backward, erroneous Cartesianism to modern, Enlightened Newtonianism thanks to the heroic intellectual efforts of figures like Voltaire.

This apparent victory in the Newton Wars of the 1730s and 1740s allowed Voltaire’s new philosophical identity to solidify. Especially crucial was the way that it allowed Voltaire’s outlaw status, which he had never fully repudiated, to be rehabilitated in the public mind as a necessary and heroic defense of philosophical truth against the enemies of error and prejudice. From this perspective, Voltaire’s critical stance could be reintegrated into traditional Old Regime society as a new kind of legitimate intellectual martyrdom. Since Voltaire also coupled his explicitly philosophical writings and polemics during the 1730s and 1740s with an equally extensive stream of plays, poems, stories, and narrative histories, many of which were orthogonal in both tone and content to the explicit campaigns of the Newton Wars, Voltaire was further able to reestablish his old identity as an Old Regime man of letters despite the scandals of these years. In 1745, Voltaire was named the Royal Historiographer of France, a title bestowed upon him as a result of his histories of Louis XIV and the Swedish King Charles II. This royal office also triggered the writing of arguably Voltaire’s most widely read and influential book, at least in the eighteenth century, Essais sur les moeurs et l’esprit des nations (1751), a pioneering work of universal history. The position also legitimated him as an officially sanctioned savant. In 1749, after the death of du Châtelet, Voltaire reinforced this impression by accepting an invitation to join the court of the young Frederick the Great in Prussia, a move that further assimilated him into the power structures of Old Regime society.

Had this assimilationist trajectory continued during the remainder of Voltaire’s life, his legacy in the history of Western philosophy might not have been so great. Yet during the 1750s, a set of new developments pulled Voltaire back toward his more radical and controversial identity and allowed him to rekindle the critical philosophe persona that he had innovated during the Newton Wars. The first step in this direction involved a dispute with his onetime colleague and ally, Pierre-Louis Moreau de Maupertuis. Maupertuis had preceded Voltaire as the first aggressive advocate for Newtonian science in France. When Voltaire was preparing his own Newtonian intervention in the Lettres philosophiques in 1732, he consulted with Maupertuis, who was by this date a pensioner in the French Royal Academy of Sciences. It was largely around Maupertuis that the young cohort of French academic Newtonians gathered during the Newton wars of 1730s and 40s, and with Voltaire fighting his own public campaigns on behalf of this same cause during the same period, the two men became the most visible faces of French Newtonianism even if they never really worked as a team in this effort. Like Voltaire, Maupertuis also shared a relationship with Emilie du Châtelet, one that included mathematical collaborations that far exceeded Voltaire’s capacities. Maupertuis was also an occasional guest at Cirey, and a correspondent with both du Châtelet and Voltaire throughout these years. But in 1745 Maupertuis surprised all of French society by moving to Berlin to accept the directorship of Frederick the Great’s newly reformed Berlin Academy of Sciences.

Maupertuis’s thought at the time of his departure for Prussia was turning toward the metaphysics and rationalist epistemology of Leibniz as a solution to certain questions in natural philosophy. Du Châtelet also shared this tendency, producing in 1740 her Institutions de physiques , a systematic attempt to wed Newtonian mechanics with Leibnizian rationalism and metaphysics. Voltaire found this Leibnizian turn dyspeptic, and he began to craft an anti-Leibnizian discourse in the 1740s that became a bulwark of his brand of Newtonianism. This placed him in opposition to Du Châtelet, even if this intellectual rift in no way soured their relationship. Yet after she died in 1749, and Voltaire joined Maupertuis at Frederick the Great’s court in Berlin, this anti-Leibnizianism became the centerpiece of a rift with Maupertuis. Voltaire’s public satire of the President of the Royal Academy of Sciences of Berlin published in late 1752, which presented Maupertuis as a despotic philosophical buffoon, forced Frederick to make a choice. He sided with Maupertuis, ordering Voltaire to either retract his libelous text or leave Berlin. Voltaire chose the latter, falling once again into the role of scandalous rebel and exile as a result of his writings.

This event proved to be Voltaire’s last official rupture with establishment authority. Rather than returning home to Paris and restoring his reputation, Voltaire instead settled in Geneva. When this austere Calvinist enclave proved completely unwelcoming, he took further steps toward independence by using his personal fortune to buy a chateau of his own in the hinterlands between France and Switzerland. Voltaire installed himself permanently at Ferney in early 1759, and from this date until his death in 1778 he made the chateau his permanent home and capital, at least in the minds of his intellectual allies, of the emerging French Enlightenment.

During this period, Voltaire also adopted what would become his most famous and influential intellectual stance, announcing himself as a member of the “party of humanity” and devoting himself toward waging war against the twin hydras of fanaticism and superstition. While the singular defense of Newtonian science had focused Voltaire’s polemical energies in the 1730s and 1740s, after 1750 the program became the defense of philosophie tout court and the defeat of its perceived enemies within the ecclesiastical and aristo-monarchical establishment. In this way, Enlightenment philosophie became associated through Voltaire with the cultural and political program encapsulated in his famous motto, “ Écrasez l’infâme! ” (“Crush the infamy!”). This entanglement of philosophy with social criticism and reformist political action, a contingent historical outcome of Voltaire’s particular intellectual career, would become his most lasting contribution to the history of philosophy.

The first cause to galvanize this new program was Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie . The first volume of this compendium of definitions appeared in 1751, and almost instantly the work became buried in the kind of scandal to which Voltaire had grown accustomed. Voltaire saw in the controversy a new call to action, and he joined forces with the project soon after its appearance, penning numerous articles that began to appear with volume 5 in 1755. Scandal continued to chase the Encyclopédie , however, and in 1759 the work’s publication privilege was revoked in France, an act that did not kill the project but forced it into illicit production in Switzerland. During these scandals, Voltaire fought vigorously alongside the project’s editors to defend the work, fusing the Encyclopédie ’s enemies, particularly the Parisian Jesuits who edited the monthly periodical the Journal de Trevoux , into a monolithic “infamy” devoted to eradicating truth and light from the world. This framing was recapitulated by the opponents of the Encyclopédie , who began to speak of the loose assemblage of authors who contributed articles to the work as a subversive coterie of philosophes devoted to undermining legitimate social and moral order.

As this polemic crystallized and grew in both energy and influence, Voltaire embraced its terms and made them his cause. He formed particularly close ties with d’Alembert, and with him began to generalize a broad program for Enlightenment centered on rallying the newly self-conscious philosophes (a term often used synonymously with the Encyclopédistes ) toward political and intellectual change. In this program, the philosophes were not unified by any shared philosophy but through a commitment to the program of defending philosophie itself against its perceived enemies. They were also imagined as activists fighting to eradicate error and superstition from the world. The ongoing defense of the Encyclopédie was one rallying point, and soon the removal of the Jesuits—the great enemies of Enlightenment, the philosophes proclaimed—became a second unifying cause. This effort achieved victory in 1763, and soon the philosophes were attempting to infiltrate the academies and other institutions of knowledge in France. One climax in this effort was reached in 1774 when the Encyclopédiste and friend of Voltaire and the philosophes , Anne-Robert Jacques Turgot, was named Controller-General of France, the most powerful ministerial position in the kingdom, by the newly crowned King Louis XVI. Voltaire and his allies had paved the way for this victory through a barrage of writings throughout the 1760s and 1770s that presented philosophie like that espoused by Turgot as an agent of enlightened reform and its critics as prejudicial defenders of an ossified tradition.

Voltaire did bring out one explicitly philosophical book in support this campaign, his Dictionnaire philosophique of 1764–1770. This book republished his articles from the original Encyclopédie while adding new entries conceived in the spirit of the original work. Yet to fully understand the brand of philosophie that Voltaire made foundational to the Enlightenment, one needs to recognize that it just as often circulated in fictional stories, satires, poems, pamphlets, and other less obviously philosophical genres. Voltaire’s most widely known text, for instance, Candide, ou l’Optimisme , first published in 1759, is a fictional story of a wandering traveler engaged in a set of farcical adventures. Yet contained in the text is a serious attack on Leibnizian philosophy, one that in many ways marks the culmination of Voltaire’s decades long attack on this philosophy started during the Newton wars. Philosophie à la Voltaire also came in the form of political activism, such as his public defense of Jean Calas who, Voltaire argued, was a victim of a despotic state and an irrational and brutal judicial system. Voltaire often attached philosophical reflection to this political advocacy, such as when he facilitated a French translation of Cesare Beccaria’s treatise on humanitarian justice and penal reform and then prefaced the work with his own essay on justice and religious toleration (Calas was a French protestant persecuted by a Catholic monarchy). Public philosophic campaigns such as these that channeled critical reason in a direct, oppositionalist way against the perceived injustices and absurdities of Old Regime life were the hallmark of philosophie as Voltaire understood the term.

Voltaire lived long enough to see some of his long-term legacies start to concretize. With the ascension of Louis XVI in 1774 and the appointment of Turgot as Controller-General, the French establishment began to embrace the philosophes and their agenda in a new way. Critics of Voltaire and his program for philosophie remained powerful, however, and they would continue to survive as the necessary backdrop to the positive image of the Enlightenment philosophe as a modernizer, progressive reformer, and courageous scourge against traditional authority that Voltaire bequeathed to later generations. During Voltaire’s lifetime, this new acceptance translated into a final return to Paris in early 1778. Here, as a frail and sickly octogenarian, Voltaire was welcomed by the city as the hero of the Enlightenment that he now personified. A statue was commissioned as a permanent shrine to his legacy, and a public performance of his play Irène was performed in a way that allowed its author to be celebrated as a national hero. Voltaire died several weeks after these events, but the canonization that they initiated has continued right up until the present.

Western philosophy was profoundly shaped by the conception of the philosophe and the program for Enlightenment philosophie that Voltaire came to personify. The model he offered of the philosophe as critical public citizen and advocate first and foremost, and as abstruse and systematic thinker only when absolutely necessary, was especially influential in the subsequent development of the European philosophy. Also influential was the example he offered of the philosopher measuring the value of any philosophy according by its ability to effect social change. In this respect, Karl Marx’s famous thesis that philosophy should aspire to change the world, not merely interpret it, owes more than a little debt Voltaire. The link between Voltaire and Marx was also established through the French revolutionary tradition, which similarly adopted Voltaire as one of its founding heroes. Voltaire was the first person to be honored with re-burial in the newly created Pantheon of the Great Men of France that the new revolutionary government created in 1791. This act served as a tribute to the connections that the revolutionaries saw between Voltaire’s philosophical program and the cause of revolutionary modernization as a whole. In a similar way, Voltaire remains today an iconic hero for everyone who sees a positive linkage between critical reason and political resistance in projects of progressive, modernizing reform.

2. Voltaire’s Enlightenment Philosophy

Voltaire’s philosophical legacy ultimately resides as much in how he practiced philosophy, and in the ends toward which he directed his philosophical activity, as in any specific doctrine or original idea. Yet the particular philosophical positions he took, and the way that he used his wider philosophical campaigns to champion certain understandings while disparaging others, did create a constellation appropriately called Voltaire’s Enlightenment philosophy. True to Voltaire’s character, this constellation is best described as a set of intellectual stances and orientations rather than as a set of doctrines or systematically defended positions. Nevertheless, others found in Voltaire both a model of the well-oriented philosophe and a set of particular philosophical positions appropriate to this stance. Each side of this equation played a key role in defining the Enlightenment philosophie that Voltaire came to personify.

Central to this complex is Voltaire’s conception of liberty. Around this category, Voltaire’s social activism and his relatively rare excursions into systematic philosophy also converged. In 1734, in the wake of the scandals triggered by the Lettres philosophiques , Voltaire wrote, but left unfinished at Cirey, a Traité de metaphysique that explored the question of human freedom in philosophical terms. The question was particularly central to European philosophical discussions at the time, and Voltaire’s work explicitly referenced thinkers like Hobbes and Leibniz while wrestling with the questions of materialism, determinism, and providential purpose that were then central to the writings of the so-called deists, figures such as John Toland and Anthony Collins. The great debate between Samuel Clarke and Leibniz over the principles of Newtonian natural philosophy was also influential as Voltaire struggled to understand the nature of human existence and ethics within a cosmos governed by rational principles and impersonal laws.

Voltaire adopted a stance in this text somewhere between the strict determinism of rationalist materialists and the transcendent spiritualism and voluntarism of contemporary Christian natural theologians. For Voltaire, humans are not deterministic machines of matter and motion, and free will thus exists. But humans are also natural beings governed by inexorable natural laws, and his ethics anchored right action in a self that possessed the natural light of reason immanently. This stance distanced him from more radical deists like Toland, and he reinforced this position by also adopting an elitist understanding of the role of religion in society. For Voltaire, those equipped to understand their own reason could find the proper course of free action themselves. But since many were incapable of such self-knowledge and self-control, religion, he claimed, was a necessary guarantor of social order. This stance distanced Voltaire from the republican politics of Toland and other materialists, and Voltaire echoed these ideas in his political musings, where he remained throughout his life a liberal, reform-minded monarchist and a skeptic with respect to republican and democratic ideas.

In the Lettres philosophiques , Voltaire had suggested a more radical position with respect to human determinism, especially in his letter on Locke, which emphasized the materialist reading of the Lockean soul that was then a popular figure in radical philosophical discourse. Some readers singled out this part of the book as the major source of its controversy, and in a similar vein the very materialist account of “ Âme ,” or the soul, which appeared in volume 1 of Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopédie , was also a flashpoint of controversy. Voltaire also defined his own understanding of the soul in similar terms in his own Dictionnaire philosophique . What these examples point to is Voltaire’s willingness, even eagerness, to publicly defend controversial views even when his own, more private and more considered writings often complicated the understanding that his more public and polemical writings insisted upon. In these cases, one often sees Voltaire defending less a carefully reasoned position on a complex philosophical problem than adopting a political position designed to assert his conviction that liberty of speech, no matter what the topic, is sacred and cannot be violated.

Voltaire never actually said “I disagree with what you say, but I will defend to the death your right to say it.” Yet the myth that associates this dictum with his name remains very powerful, and one still hears his legacy invoked through the redeclaration of this pronouncement that he never actually declared. Part of the deep cultural tie that joins Voltaire to this dictum is the fact that even while he did not write these precise words, they do capture, however imprecisely, the spirit of his philosophy of liberty. In his voluminous correspondence especially, and in the details of many of his more polemical public texts, one does find Voltaire articulating a view of intellectual and civil liberty that makes him an unquestioned forerunner of modern civil libertarianism. He never authored any single philosophical treatise on this topic, however, yet the memory of his life and philosophical campaigns was influential in advancing these ideas nevertheless. Voltaire’s influence is palpably present, for example, in Kant’s famous argument in his essay “What is Enlightenment?” that Enlightenment stems from the free and public use of critical reason, and from the liberty that allows such critical debate to proceed untrammeled. The absence of a singular text that anchors this linkage in Voltaire’s collected works in no way removes the unmistakable presence of Voltaire’s influence upon Kant’s formulation.

Voltaire’s notion of liberty also anchored his hedonistic morality, another key feature of Voltaire’s Enlightenment philosophy. One vehicle for this philosophy was Voltaire’s salacious poetry, a genre that both reflected in its eroticism and sexual innuendo the lived culture of libertinism that was an important feature of Voltaire’s biography. But Voltaire also contributed to philosophical libertinism and hedonism through his celebration of moral freedom through sexual liberty. Voltaire’s avowed hedonism became a central feature of his wider philosophical identity since his libertine writings and conduct were always invoked by those who wanted to indict him for being a reckless subversive devoted to undermining legitimate social order. Voltaire’s refusal to defer to such charges, and his vigor in opposing them through a defense of the very libertinism that was used against him, also injected a positive philosophical program into these public struggles that was very influential. In particular, through his cultivation of a happily libertine persona, and his application of philosophical reason toward the moral defense of this identity, often through the widely accessible vehicles of poetry and witty prose, Voltaire became a leading force in the wider Enlightenment articulation of a morality grounded in the positive valuation of personal, and especially bodily, pleasure, and an ethics rooted in a hedonistic calculus of maximizing pleasure and minimizing pain. He also advanced this cause by sustaining an unending attack upon the repressive and, to his mind, anti-human demands of traditional Christian asceticism, especially priestly celibacy, and the moral codes of sexual restraint and bodily self-abnegation that were still central to the traditional moral teachings of the day.

This same hedonistic ethics was also crucial to the development of liberal political economy during the Enlightenment, and Voltaire applied his own libertinism toward this project as well. In the wake of the scandals triggered by Mandeville’s famous argument in The Fable of the Bees (a poem, it should be remembered) that the pursuit of private vice, namely greed, leads to public benefits, namely economic prosperity, a French debate about the value of luxury as a moral good erupted that drew Voltaire’s pen. In the 1730s, he drafted a poem called Le Mondain that celebrated hedonistic worldly living as a positive force for society, and not as the corrupting element that traditional Christian morality held it to be. In his Essay sur les moeurs he also joined with other Enlightenment historians in celebrating the role of material acquisition and commerce in advancing the progress of civilization. Adam Smith would famously make similar arguments in his founding tract of Enlightenment liberalism, On the Wealth of Nations , published in 1776. Voltaire was certainly no great contributor to the political economic science that Smith practiced, but he did contribute to the wider philosophical campaigns that made the concepts of liberty and hedonistic morality central to their work both widely known and more generally accepted.

The ineradicable good of personal and philosophical liberty is arguably the master theme in Voltaire’s philosophy, and if it is, then two other themes are closely related to it. One is the importance of skepticism, and the second is the importance of empirical science as a solvent to dogmatism and the pernicious authority it engenders.

Voltaire’s skepticism descended directly from the neo-Pyrrhonian revival of the Renaissance, and owes a debt in particular to Montaigne, whose essays wedded the stance of doubt with the positive construction of a self grounded in philosophical skepticism. Pierre Bayle’s skepticism was equally influential, and what Voltaire shared with these forerunners, and what separated him from other strands of skepticism, such as the one manifest in Descartes, is the insistence upon the value of the skeptical position in its own right as a final and complete philosophical stance. Among the philosophical tendencies that Voltaire most deplored, in fact, were those that he associated most powerfully with Descartes who, he believed, began in skepticism but then left it behind in the name of some positive philosophical project designed to eradicate or resolve it. Such urges usually led to the production of what Voltaire liked to call “philosophical romances,” which is to say systematic accounts that overcome doubt by appealing to the imagination and its need for coherent explanations. Such explanations, Voltaire argued, are fictions, not philosophy, and the philosopher needs to recognize that very often the most philosophical explanation of all is to offer no explanation at all.

Such skepticism often acted as bulwark for Voltaire’s defense of liberty since he argued that no authority, no matter how sacred, should be immune to challenge by critical reason. Voltaire’s views on religion as manifest in his private writings are complex, and based on the evidence of these texts it would be wrong to call Voltaire an atheist, or even an anti-Christian so long as one accepts a broad understanding of what Christianity can entail. But even if his personal religious views were subtle, Voltaire was unwavering in his hostility to church authority and the power of the clergy. For similar reasons, he also grew as he matured ever more hostile toward the sacred mysteries upon which monarchs and Old Regime aristocratic society based their authority. In these cases, Voltaire’s skepticism was harnessed to his libertarian convictions through his continual effort to use critical reason as a solvent for these “superstitions” and the authority they anchored. The philosophical authority of romanciers such as Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibniz was similarly subjected to the same critique, and here one sees how the defense of skepticism and liberty, more than any deeply held opposition to religiosity per se, was often the most powerful motivator for Voltaire.

From this perspective, Voltaire might fruitfully be compared with Socrates, another founding figure in Western philosophy who made a refusal to declaim systematic philosophical positions a central feature of his philosophical identity. Socrates’s repeated assertion that he knew nothing was echoed in Voltaire’s insistence that the true philosopher is the one who dares not to know and then has the courage to admit his ignorance publicly. Voltaire was also, like Socrates, a public critic and controversialist who defined philosophy primarily in terms of its power to liberate individuals from domination at the hands of authoritarian dogmatism and irrational prejudice. Yet while Socrates championed rigorous philosophical dialectic as the agent of this emancipation, Voltaire saw this same dialectical rationalism at the heart of the dogmatism that he sought to overcome. Voltaire often used satire, mockery and wit to undermine the alleged rigor of philosophical dialectic, and while Socrates saw this kind of rhetorical word play as the very essence of the erroneous sophism that he sought to alleviate, Voltaire cultivated linguistic cleverness as a solvent to the false and deceptive dialectic that anchored traditional philosophy.

Against the acceptance of ignorance that rigorous skepticism often demanded, and against the false escape from it found in sophistical knowledge—or what Voltaire called imaginative philosophical romances—Voltaire offered a different solution than the rigorous dialectical reasoning of Socrates: namely, the power and value of careful empirical science. Here one sees the debt that Voltaire owed to the currents of Newtonianism that played such a strong role in launching his career. Voltaire’s own critical discourse against imaginative philosophical romances originated, in fact, with English and Dutch Newtonians, many of whom were expatriate French Huguenots, who developed these tropes as rhetorical weapons in their battles with Leibniz and European Cartesians who challenged the innovations of Newtonian natural philosophy. In his Principia Mathematica (1687; 2 nd rev. edition 1713), Newton had offered a complete mathematical and empirical description of how celestial and terrestrial bodies behaved. Yet when asked to explain how bodies were able to act in the way that he mathematically and empirically demonstrated that they did, Newton famously replied “I feign no hypotheses.” From the perspective of traditional natural philosophy, this was tantamount to hand waving since offering rigorous causal accounts of the nature of bodies in motion was the very essence of this branch of the sciences. Newton’s major philosophical innovation rested, however, in challenging this very epistemological foundation, and the assertion and defense of Newton’s position against its many critics, not least by Voltaire, became arguably the central dynamic of philosophical change in the first half of the eighteenth century.

While Newtonian epistemology admitted of many variations, at its core rested a new skepticism about the validity of apriori rationalist accounts of nature and a new assertion of brute empirical fact as a valid philosophical understanding in its own right. European Natural philosophers in the second half of the seventeenth century had thrown out the metaphysics and physics of Aristotle with its four part causality and teleological understanding of bodies, motion and the cosmic order. In its place, however, a new mechanical causality was introduced that attempted to explain the world in equally comprehensive terms through the mechanisms of an inert matter acting by direct contact and action alone. This approach lead to the vortical account of celestial mechanics, a view that held material bodies to be swimming in an ethereal sea whose action pushed and pulled objects in the manner we observe. What could not be observed, however, was the ethereal sea itself, or the other agents of this supposedly comprehensive mechanical cosmos. Yet rationality nevertheless dictated that such mechanisms must exist since without them philosophy would be returned to the occult causes of the Aristotelian natural tendencies and teleological principles. Figuring out what these point-contact mechanisms were and how they worked was, therefore, the charge of the new mechanical natural philosophy of the late seventeenth century. Figures such as Descartes, Huygens, and Leibniz established their scientific reputations through efforts to realize this goal.

Newton pointed natural philosophy in a new direction. He offered mathematical analysis anchored in inescapable empirical fact as the new foundation for a rigorous account of the cosmos. From this perspective, the great error of both Aristotelian and the new mechanical natural philosophy was its failure to adhere strictly enough to empirical facts. Vortical mechanics, for example, claimed that matter was moved by the action of an invisible agent, yet this, the Newtonians began to argue, was not to explain what is really happening but to imagine a fiction that gives us a speciously satisfactory rational explanation of it. Natural philosophy needs to resist the allure of such rational imaginings and to instead deal only with the empirically provable. Moreover, the Newtonians argued, if a set of irrefutable facts cannot be explained other then by accepting the brute facticity of their truth, this is not a failure of philosophical explanation so much as a devotion to appropriate rigor. Such epistemological battles became especially intense around Newton’s theory of universal gravitation. Few questioned that Newton had demonstrated an irrefutable mathematical law whereby bodies appear to attract one another in relation to their masses and in inverse relation to the square of the distance between them. But was this rigorous mathematical and empirical description a philosophical account of bodies in motion? Critics such as Leibniz said no, since mathematical description was not the same thing as philosophical explanation, and Newton refused to offer an explanation of how and why gravity operated the way that it did. The Newtonians countered that phenomenal descriptions were scientifically adequate so long as they were grounded in empirical facts, and since no facts had yet been discerned that explained what gravity is or how it works, no scientific account of it was yet possible. They further insisted that it was enough that gravity did operate the way that Newton said it did, and that this was its own justification for accepting his theory. They further mocked those who insisted on dreaming up chimeras like the celestial vortices as explanations for phenomena when no empirical evidence existed to support of such theories.

The previous summary describes the general core of the Newtonian position in the intense philosophical contests of the first decades of the eighteenth century. It also describes Voltaire’s own stance in these same battles. His contribution, therefore, was not centered on any innovation within these very familiar Newtonian themes; rather, it was his accomplishment to become a leading evangelist for this new Newtonian epistemology, and by consequence a major reason for its widespread dissemination and acceptance in France and throughout Europe. A comparison with David Hume’s role in this same development might help to illuminate the distinct contributions of each. Both Hume and Voltaire began with the same skepticism about rationalist philosophy, and each embraced the Newtonian criterion that made empirical fact the only guarantor of truth in philosophy. Yet Hume’s target remained traditional philosophy, and his contribution was to extend skepticism all the way to the point of denying the feasibility of transcendental philosophy itself. This argument would famously awake Kant’s dogmatic slumbers and lead to the reconstitution of transcendental philosophy in new terms, but Voltaire had different fish to fry. His attachment was to the new Newtonian empirical scientists, and while he was never more than a dilettante scientist himself, his devotion to this form of natural inquiry made him in some respects the leading philosophical advocate and ideologist for the new empirico-scientific conception of philosophy that Newton initiated.

For Voltaire (and many other eighteenth-century Newtonians) the most important project was defending empirical science as an alternative to traditional natural philosophy. This involved sharing in Hume’s critique of abstract rationalist systems, but it also involved the very different project of defending empirical induction and experimental reasoning as the new epistemology appropriate for a modern Enlightened philosophy. In particular, Voltaire fought vigorously against the rationalist epistemology that critics used to challenge Newtonian reasoning. His famous conclusion in Candide , for example, that optimism was a philosophical chimera produced when dialectical reason remains detached from brute empirical facts owed a great debt to his Newtonian convictions. His alternative offered in the same text of a life devoted to simple tasks with clear, tangible, and most importantly useful ends was also derived from the utilitarian discourse that Newtonians also used to justify their science. Voltaire’s campaign on behalf of smallpox inoculation, which began with his letter on the topic in the Lettres philosophiques , was similarly grounded in an appeal to the facts of the case as an antidote to the fears generated by logical deductions from seemingly sound axiomatic principles. All of Voltaire’s public campaigns, in fact, deployed empirical fact as the ultimate solvent for irrational prejudice and blind adherence to preexisting understandings. In this respect, his philosophy as manifest in each was deeply indebted to the epistemological convictions he gleaned from Newtonianism.

Voltaire also contributed directly to the new relationship between science and philosophy that the Newtonian revolution made central to Enlightenment modernity. Especially important was his critique of metaphysics and his argument that it be eliminated from any well-ordered science. At the center of the Newtonian innovations in natural philosophy was the argument that questions of body per se were either irrelevant to, or distracting from, a well focused natural science. Against Leibniz, for example, who insisted that all physics begin with an accurate and comprehensive conception of the nature of bodies as such, Newton argued that the character of bodies was irrelevant to physics since this science should restrict itself to a quantified description of empirical effects only and resist the urge to speculate about that which cannot be seen or measured. This removal of metaphysics from physics was central to the overall Newtonian stance toward science, but no one fought more vigorously for it, or did more to clarify the distinction and give it a public audience than Voltaire.

The battles with Leibnizianism in the 1740s were the great theater for Voltaire’s work in this regard. In 1740, responding to Du Châtelet’s efforts in her Institutions de physiques to reconnect metaphysics and physics through a synthesis of Leibniz with Newton, Voltaire made his opposition to such a project explicit in reviews and other essays he published. He did the same during the brief revival of the so-called “vis viva controversy” triggered by du Châtelet’s treatise, defending the empirical and mechanical conception of body and force against those who defended Leibniz’s more metaphysical conception of the same thing. In the same period, Voltaire also composed a short book entitled La Metaphysique de Newton , publishing it in 1740 as an implicit counterpoint to Châtelet’s Institutions . This tract did not so much articulate Newton’s metaphysics as celebrate the fact that he avoided practicing such speculations altogether. It also accused Leibniz of becoming deluded by his zeal to make metaphysics the foundation of physics. In the definitive 1745 edition of his Éléments de la philosophie de Newton , Voltaire also appended his tract on Newton’s metaphysics as the book’s introduction, thus framing his own understanding of the relationship between metaphysics and empirical science in direct opposition to Châtelet’s Leibnizian understanding of the same. He also added personal invective and satire to this same position in his indictment of Maupertuis in the 1750s, linking Maupertuis’s turn toward metaphysical approaches to physics in the 1740s with his increasingly deluded philosophical understanding and his authoritarian manner of dealing with his colleagues and critics.

While Voltaire’s attacks on Maupertuis crossed the line into ad hominem , at their core was a fierce defense of the way that metaphysical reasoning both occludes and deludes the work of the physical scientist. Moreover, to the extent that eighteenth-century Newtonianism provoked two major trends in later philosophy, first the reconstitution of transcendental philosophy à la Kant through his “Copernican Revolution” that relocated the remains of metaphysics in the a priori categories of reason, and second, the marginalization of metaphysics altogether through the celebration of philosophical positivism and the anti-speculative scientific method that anchored it, Voltaire should be seen as a major progenitor of the latter. By also attaching what many in the nineteenth century saw as Voltaire’s proto-positivism to his celebrated campaigns to eradicate priestly and aristo-monarchical authority through the debunking of the “irrational superstitions” that appeared to anchor such authority, Voltaire’s legacy also cemented the alleged linkage that joined positivist science on the one hand with secularizing disenchantment and dechristianization on the other. In this way, Voltaire should be seen as the initiator of a philosophical tradition that runs from him to Auguste Comte and Charles Darwin, and then on to Karl Popper and Richard Dawkins in the twentieth century.

Because of Voltaire’s celebrity, efforts to collect and canonize his writings began immediately after his death, and still continue today. The result has been the production of three major collections of his writings including his vast correspondence, the last unfinished. Together these constitute the authoritative corpus of Voltaire’s written work.

  • Oeuvres complètes de Voltaire , edited by A. Beuchot. 72 vols. Paris: Lefevre, 1829–1840.
  • Oeuvres complètes de Voltaire , edited by L.E.D. Moland and G. Bengesco. 52 vols. Paris: Garnier Frères, 1877–1885.
  • Oeuvres complètes de Voltaire , edited by Theodore Besterman. 135 vols. (projected) Geneva, Banbury, and Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, 1968–.

Collections of Writings

  • The Works of Voltaire: A Contemporary Version , William F. Fleming (ed. and tr.), 21 vols., New York: E.R. Du Mont, 1901. [Complete edition available at the Online Library of Liberty ]
  • The Portable Voltaire , Ben Ray Redman (ed.), New York: Penguin Books, 1977.
  • Selected Works of Voltaire , Joseph McCabe (ed.), London: Watts, 2007.
  • Shorter Writings of Voltaire , J.I. Rodale (ed.), New York: A.S. Barnes, 1960.
  • Voltaire in his Letters, Being a Selection of his Correspondence , S.G. Tallentyre (tr.), Honolulu, HI: University Press of the Pacific, 2004.
  • Voltaire on Religion: Selected Writings , Kenneth W. Applegate (ed.), New York: F. Ungar, 1974.
  • Voltaire: Selected Writings , Christopher Thacker (ed.), London: Dent, 1995.
  • Voltaire: Selections , Paul Edwards (ed.), New York: Macmillan, 1989.
  • Translations of Voltaire’s major plays are found in: The Works of Voltaire: A Contemporary Version , William F. Fleming (ed. and tr.), New York: E.R. Du Mont, 1901. [Complete edition available at the Online Library of Liberty ]
  • Seven Plays (Mérope (1737), Olympia (1761), Alzire (1734), Orestes (1749), Oedipus (1718), Zaire, Caesar) , William Fleming (tr.), New York: Howard Fertig, 1988.
  • The Age of Louis XIV (1733) and other Selected Writings , J.H. Brumfitt (ed.), New York: Twayne, 1963.
  • The Age of Louis XIV (1733) , Martyn P. Pollack (tr.), London and New York: Dutton, 1978.
  • History of Charles XII, King of Sweden (1727) , Honolulu, HI: University Press of the Pacific, 2002.
  • History of Charles XII, King of Sweden (1727) , Antonia White and Ragnhild Marie Hatton (eds.), New York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1993.
  • The Philosophy of History (1764) , New York: The Philosophical Library, 1965.

Essays, Letters, and Stories

  • Vol. 1: The Huron (1771), The History of Jenni (1774), The One-eyed Street Porter, Cosi-sancta (1715), An Incident of Memory (1773), The Travels of Reason (1774), The Man with Forty Crowns (1768), Timon (1755), The King of Boutan (1761), and The City of Cashmere (1760).
  • Vol. 2: The Letters of Amabed (1769), The Blind Judges of Colors (1766), The Princess of Babylon (1768), The Ears of Lord Chesterfield and Chaplain Goudman (1775), Story of a Good Brahman (1759), An Indian Adventure (1764), and Zadig, or, Destiny (1757).
  • Vol. 3: Micromegas (1738), Candide, or Optimism (1758), The World as it Goes (1750), The White and the Black (1764), Jeannot and Colin (1764), The Travels of Scarmentado (1756), The White Bull (1772), Memnon (1750), Plato’s Dream (1737), Bababec and the Fakirs (1750), and The Two Consoled Ones (1756).
  • The English Essays of 1727 , David Williams and Richard Walker (eds.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, 1996.
  • Epistle of M. Voltaire to the King of Prussia (1738) , Glasgow, 1967.
  • The History of the Travels of Scarmentado (1756) , Glasgow: The College Press, 1969.
  • Micromégas and other Short Fictions (1738), Theo Cuffe and Haydn Mason (eds.), London and New York: Penguin Books, 2002.
  • The Princess of Babylon (1768) , London: Signet Books, 1969.
  • The Virgin of Orleans, or Joan of Arc (1755) , Howard Nelson (tr.), Denver: A. Swallow, 1965.
  • Voltaire. Essay on Milton (1727) , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1954.
  • Voltaire’s Romances , New York: P. Eckler, 1986.
  • Zadig, or L’Ingénu (1757), London: Penguin Books, 1984.
  • Zadig, or the Book of Fate (1757) , New York: Garland, 1974.
  • Zadig, or The Book of Fate an Oriental History (1757) , Woodbridge, CT: Research Publications, 1982.
  • The Calas Affair: A Treatise on Tolerance (1762) , Brian Masters (ed.), London: The Folio Society, 1994.
  • The Sermon of the Fifty (1759) , J.A.R. Séguin (ed.), Jersey City, NJ: R. Paxton, 1963.
  • A Treatise on Toleration and Other Essays , Joseph McCabe (ed.), Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1994.
  • A Treatise on Tolerance and other Writings , edited by Brian Masters, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994
  • Voltaire. Political Writings , edited by David Williams, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994

Editions of Major Individual Works

  • Translated John Hanna. London: Cass, 1967.
  • Birmingham, AL: Gryphon Editions, 1991.
  • Edited by Theodore Besterman. London: Penguin Books, 2002.
  • Translated by Peter Gay. New York: Basic Books, 1962.
  • Philosophical Dictionary: A Compendium , Wade Baskin (ed.), New York: Philosophical Library, 1961.
  • Philosophical Dictionary: Selections , Chicago: The Great Books Foundation, 1965.
  • John Leigh and Prudence L. Steiner (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2007.
  • Leonard Tancock (ed.), London and New York: Penguin Books, 2003.
  • Ernest Dilworth (ed.), Mineola, NY: Dover, 2003.
  • Nicholas Cronk (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press, 1994.
  • F.A. Taylor (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1946.
  • Harvard Classics, Vol. 34, Part 2. [ Available online from Bartleby.com ]
  • Voltaire’s Letters on the Quakers (1727) , Philadelphia: William H. Allen, 1953.
  • C.H.R. Niven (ed.), London: Longman, 1980.
  • Candide and other Writings , Haskell M. Block (ed.), New York: Modern Library, 1985.
  • Richard Aldington, Ernest Dilworth, and others (eds.), New York: Modern Library, 1992.
  • Shane Weller (ed.), New York: Dover, 1993.
  • Candide: A Dual Language Book , New York: Barnes & Noble Books, 1993.
  • Robert Martin Adams (ed.), New York: W.W. Norton, 1996.
  • Electronic Scholarly Publishing Project, 1998. [Available online at Electronic Scholarly Publishing Project ]
  • Daniel Gordon (ed.), Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 1999.
  • Candide and Related Texts , David Wooton (ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2000.
  • Lowell Bair (ed.), New York: Bantam Books, 2003.
  • Candide & Zadig , Lester G. Crocker (ed.), New York: Pocket Books, 2005.
  • Raffael Burton (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007.
  • Theo Cuffe (ed.), London and New York: Penguin Books, 2007.
  • Candide and other Stories , Roger Pearson (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
  • Candide, Zadig, and Selected Stories , Donald Frame (tr. and ed.), New York: Signet Classic, 2009.

The scholarly literature on Voltaire is vast, and growing larger every day. The summary here, therefore, will be largely restricted to scholarly books, with only a few articles of singular import listed. The Voltaire Foundation’s series Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century changed its name in 2013 to Oxford University Studies on Enlightenment . The original series published over 450 volumes, many related to Voltaire, and while the new title reflects a change toward a broader publishing agenda, it remains, along with Cahier Voltaire published by La Fondation Voltaire à Ferney, the best periodical source for new scholarship on Voltaire.

  • Aldridge, Alfred Owen, 1975, Voltaire and the Century of Light , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Badinter, Elizabeth, 1983, Émilie, Émilie, l’ambition féminine au XVIIIe siècle , Paris: Flammarion.
  • –––, 1999–2002, Les Passions intellectuelles , 2 volumes, Paris: Fayard.
  • Barber, W.H., 1955, Leibniz in France from Arnauld to Voltaire: A Study in French Reactions to Leibnizianism 1670–1760 , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Barrell, Rex A., 1988, Bolingbroke and France , Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
  • Besterman, Theodore, 1969, Voltaire , New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World.
  • Bird, Stephen, 2000, Reinventing Voltaire: The Politics of Commemoration in Nineteenth-century France , Oxford: Oxford University Studies on Enlightenment.
  • Brooks, Richard A., 1964, Voltaire and Leibniz , Geneva: Droz.
  • Brown, Harcourt, 1947, Voltaire and the Royal Society of London , Toronto: University of Toronto Quarterly.
  • Brumfitt, J.H., 1970, Voltaire: historian , London: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1973, The French Enlightenment , Cambridge: Schenkman Pub. Co.
  • Brunel, Lucien, 1967, Les Philosophes et l’académie française au dix-huitième siècle , Genève: Slatkine Reprints.
  • Brunet, Pierre, 1931, L’introduction des théories de Newton en France au XVIIIe siècle , Paris: A. Blanchard.
  • Collins, J. Churton, 1908, Voltaire, Montesquieu, and Rousseau in England , London: E. Nash.
  • Conlon, Pierre M., 1961, Voltaire’s literary career from 1728 to 1750 , Genève: Institut et Musée Voltaire.
  • Cottret, Bernard, 1992, Bolingbroke: exil et écriture au siècle des Lumières , Paris: Klincksieck.
  • Cronk, Nicolas, 2009, The Cambridge Companion to Voltaire , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2014, Voltaire: a very short introduction , Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation.
  • Darnton, Robert, 1979, The Business of Enlightenment: The Publishing History of the Encyclopédie , 1775–1800, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1982, The Literary Underground of the Old Regime , Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Dickinson, H.T., 1970, Bolingbroke , London: Constable.
  • Dieckmann, Herbert, 1943, Le Philosophe: Texts and Interpretations , (Washington University Studies, New Series, Language and Literature, no. 18), St. Louis: Washington University Press.
  • Duchet, Michèle, 1971, Anthropologie et histoire au siècle des lumières Buffon, Voltaire, Rousseau, Helvetius, Diderot , Paris: F. Maspero.
  • Ehrman, Esther, 1986, Mme. du Châtelet: Scientist, Philosopher and Feminist of the Enlightenment , Leamington [Spa]: Berg.
  • Gandt, François de, 2001, Cirey dans la vie intellectuelle: la réception de Newton en France , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Gardiner Janik, Linda, 1982, “Searching for the Metaphysics of Science: The Structure and Composition of Mme. Du Châtelet’s Institutions de physiques , 1737–1740”, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century , 201: 85–113.
  • Gay, Peter, 1954, The Party of Humanity: Essays in the French Enlightenment , New York: Knopf.
  • Gay, Peter, 1969, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation (Volume 1: The Science of Freedom ), New York: Knopf.
  • –––, 1977, The Enlightenment: An Interpretation (Volume 2: The Rise of Modern Paganism ), New York: Knopf 1977.
  • –––, 1988, Voltaire’s Politics: The Poet as Realist , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Guerlac, Henry, 1981, Newton on the Continent , Ithaca.
  • Gurrado, Antonio, 2013, Voltaire cattolico , Torino: Lindau.
  • Hagengruber, Ruth (ed.), 2011, Emilie du Châtelet between Leibniz and Newton , Dordrecht: Springer.
  • Ḥadīd, Javādī, 2012, Voltaire et l’Islam , Ozoir la Ferriere : Albouraq.
  • Hellman, Lilian, 1980, Dorothy Parker, John La Touche, Richard Wilbur, and Leonard Bernstein, 1956–1957, Candide, An Operetta in Two Acts , New York: Jaini Publications.
  • Hutchison, Ross, 1991, Locke in France: 1688–1734 , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Iltis, Carolyn, 1977, “Madame du Châtelet’s metaphysics and mechanics”, Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science , 8: 29–48.
  • Israel, Jonathan, 2000, The Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650–1750 , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2006, Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity, and the Emancipation of Man 1670–1752 , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2009, A Revolution of the Mind: Radical Enlightenment and the Intellectual Origins of Modern Democracy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2011, Democratic Enlightenment: Philosophy, Revolution, and Human Rights 1750–1790 , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2014, Revolutionary Ideas: An Intellectual History of the French Revolution from The Rights of Man to Robespierre , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Jacob, Margaret, 1981, The Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons, and Republicans , London: Cornerstone Book Publishers.
  • Kramnick, Isaac, 1968, Bolingbroke and His Circle: The Politics of Nostalgia in the Age of Walpole , Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Lanson, Gustave, 1894, Histoire de la littérature française , Paris: Hachette.
  • Lanson, Gustave, 1906, Voltaire , Paris: Hachette.
  • Libby, Margaret Sherwood, 1935, The Attitude of Voltaire to Magic and the Sciences , New York: Columbia University Press, 1935.
  • Lilti, Antoine, 2005, Le monde des salons. Sociabilité et mondanité à Paris au XVIIIe siècle , Paris: Fayard.
  • Mason, Haydn Trevor, 1963, Pierre Bayle and Voltaire , London: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 1975, Voltaire , New York: St. Martin’s.
  • Masseau, Didier, 1994, L’Invention de l’intellectual dans l’Europe du XVIIIe siècle , Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Mattei, Silvia, 2010, Voltaire et les voyages de la raison , Paris: Harmattan.
  • Maurois, André, 1935, Voltaire , Paris: Gallimard.
  • Mauzi, Robert, 1960, L’idée du bonheur dans la litterature et la pensée francaises au XVIIIe siècle , Paris: A. Colin.
  • McKenna, Antony, 1994, Écraser l’infame, 1759–1770 , Voltaire en son temps (Volume 4), René Pomeau (ed.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • McMahon, Darrin M., 2001, Enemies of the Enlightenment: The French Counter-enlightenment and the Making of Modernity , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • McNutt, Jennifer Powell, 2013, Calvin meets Voltaire: the clergy of Geneva in the age of enlightenment, 1685–1798 , Burlington: Ashgate.
  • Melton, James Van Horn, 2001, The Rise of the Public in Enlightenment Europe , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Méricam-Bourdet, Myrtille, 2012, Voltaire et l’écriture de l’histoire: un enjeu politique , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Mervaud, Christiane, 1991, De la cour au jardin, 1750–1759 , Voltaire en son temps (Volume 3), René Pomeau (ed.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Mitchell, Harvey, 2104, Voltaire’s Jews and modern Jewish identity: rethinking the Enlightenment , London: Routledge.
  • Morize, André, 1909, L’Apologie du luxe au XVIIIe Siècle: “Le Mondain” et ses Sources , Paris: H. Didier.
  • Neiertz, Patrick, 2012, Voltaire et l’économie politique , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Northeast, Catherine M., 1991, The Parisian Jesuits and the Enlightenment, 1700–1762 , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Orieux, Jean, 1966, Voltaire, ou la Royauté de l’esprit , Paris: Flammarion.
  • Palmer, Robert R., 1939, Catholics and Unbelievers in 18 th Century France , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Pappas, John N., 1957, Berthier’s Journal de Trevoux and the Philosophes (Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century, Volume 3), Geneva: Institut and Musée Voltaire.
  • –––, 1962, Voltaire and d’Alembert , Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
  • Pearson, Roger, 1993, The Fables of Reason: A Study of Voltaire’s “Contes philosophiques” , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 2005, Voltaire Almighty: A Life in Pursuit of Freedom , London: Bloomsbury Publishing.
  • Perry, Norma, 1975, Sir Everard Fawkener, friend and correspondent of Voltaire , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Pettit, Alexander, 1997, Illusory Consensus: Bolingbroke and the Polemical Responses to Walpole, 1730–1737 , Newark: University of Delaware Press.
  • Pomeau, René, 1969, La réligion de Voltaire , Paris: Nizet.
  • –––, 1985, D’Arouet à Voltaire, 1694–1734 , Voltaire en son temps (Volume 1), René Pomeau (ed.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • –––, 1994, On a voulu l’enterrer, 1770–1791 , Voltaire en son temps (Volume 5), René Pomeau (ed.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Pomeau, René (ed)., 1985–1994, Voltaire en son temps , 5 vols., Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Popkin, Richard Henry, 1979, The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Proust, Jacques, 1962, Diderot et l’Encyclopédie , Paris: Slatkine.
  • Rasmussen, Dennis Carl, 2014, The pragmatic enlightenment: recovering the liberalism of Hume, Smith, Montesquieu, and Voltaire , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Rousseau, André Michel, 1976, L’Angleterre et Voltaire (1718–1789) , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Saigey, Émile, 1873, Les sciences au XVIIIe siècle: la physique de Voltaire , Paris: G. Baillière.
  • Schlereth, Thomas J., 1977, The cosmopolitan ideal in Enlightenment thought, its form and function in the ideas of Franklin, Hume, and Voltaire, 1694–1790 , South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Shank, J.B., 2008, The Newton Wars and the Beginning of the French Enlightenment , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Sharpe, Matthew, 2015, “On a Neglected Argument in French Philosophy: Sceptical Humanism in Montaigne, Voltaire and Camus”, Critical Horizons: A Journal of Philosophy and Social Theory , 16(1): 1–26.
  • Spink, John Stephenson, 1960, French Free-thought from Gassendi to Voltaire , London: University of London, Athlone Press.
  • Terrall, Mary, 2002, The Man Who Flattened the Earth: Maupertuis and the Sciences in the Enlightenment , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Tlili, Mahbouba Saï, 2009, Voltaire et l’Islam Tunis: Arabesques.
  • Torrey, Norman L., 1930, Voltaire and the English Deists , New Haven: Yale University Press, 2 nd edition, Hamden, CT: Archon Books, 1967.
  • –––,1938, The Spirit of Voltaire , New York: Russell and Russell, 2 nd edition, 1968.
  • Undank, Jack, 1989, “Portrait of the Philosopher as Tramp”, in A New History of French Literature , Dennis Hollier (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989, pp. 421–428.
  • Vaillot, René, 1988, Avec madame Du Châtelet, 1734–1749 , Voltaire en son temps (Volume 2), René Pomeau (ed.), Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
  • Van Kley, Dale, 1975, The Jansenists and the Expulsion of the Jesuits in France, 1757–1767 , New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Vercruysse, Jeroom, 1966, Voltaire et la Holland, Genève: Institut et Musée Voltaire.
  • Vernière, Paul, 1954, Spinoza et la pensée française avant la Révolution , Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Wade, Ira Owen, 1938, The Clandestine Organization and Diffusion of Philosophic Ideas in France from 1700 to 1750 , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1941, Voltaire and Madame du Châtelet: An Essay on the Intellectual Activity at Cirey , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1947, Studies on Voltaire with Some Unpublished Papers of Mme. du Châtelet , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1969, The Intellectual Devevelopment of Voltaire , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Zinsser, Judith, 2006, La Dame d’Esprit: A Biography of the Marquise du Châtelet , New York: Viking.
  • Zinsser, Judith and Hayes, Julie (eds.), 2006, Emilie du Châtelet: Rewriting Enlightenment Philosophy and Science , Oxford: Voltaire Foundation.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Château de Cirey , (Champagne, France), Residence of Voltaire.
  • Institut et Musée Voltaire , Geneva.
  • La Société Voltaire .
  • The Voltaire Foundation , Oxford University.
  • The Best Voltaire Books , recommended by Nicholas Cronk.

Clarke, Samuel | Descartes, René | hedonism | Hume, David: Newtonianism and Anti-Newtonianism | Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm | liberty: positive and negative | Newton, Isaac | skepticism

Copyright © 2020 by J.B. Shank < jbshank @ umn . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

  • International edition
  • Australia edition
  • Europe edition

Portrait of Catherine the Great

How Voltaire praised the 'enlightened despot' Catherine the Great

They are the heartfelt correspondence from the great acerbic wit of the European Enlightenment to the last Russian empress, in which he praises her authoritarian style and mocks the extravagances of her French counterparts.

For years, the letters from Voltaire to Catherine the Great have been hidden away in a private collection - the contents a mystery. But now, courtesy of a Moscow art dealer, they will be returned to Russia , where their musings and advice may provide solace to the current Kremlin resident, Vladimir Putin, himself accused by critics of an authoritarian style.

Alexander Khochinsky, a Russian art dealer, paid a record €583,200 (£400,000) in Paris for the 26 letters written by the French satirist to Catherine II. Yesterday, he refused to say on whose behalf he had bought the archive. He said: "I cannot say the name of the person, but they are very important and in Russia." He added that the purchaser was not one of Russia's oligarchs. "I did a lot of work to get the archive at the best conditions and price," he said.

The Kremlin has recently promoted the return to Moscow of valuable artefacts from Russia's history, many of which were lost to foreign collectors during the the last century. The oligarch Viktor Vekselberg paid a reported $100m (£54m) in 2004 for the Fabergé eggs which he then returned to Russia.

Mr Khochinsky said he had not read the letters, dated 1768 to 1777, but thought they contained information that would help the "European direction of Russia".

Thomas Bompard, a manuscript expert at Sotheby's in Paris who looked after the archive, said: "Voltaire and Catherine never met, but the relationship between these great characters of the 18th century was conducted through these letters."

The most telling comments in the letter for today's Russia refer to Catherine's governing style. Mr Bompard said Voltaire, who lambasted the French monarchy during the Enlightenment for its excesses, approved of her role as an "enlightened despot".

Catherine, who ruled Russia for three decades until her death in 1796, viewed herself a patron of the arts and liberty, and a "philosopher on the throne", but has been criticised for the little she did for the millions of peasants in her empire.

Voltaire supported her military endeavours, including her war against the Turks. Mr Bompard said that after Louis XVI's wedding to Marie Antoinette, the monarch, soon to be deposed by the French revolution, celebrated by setting off hundreds of fireworks which apparently killed many bystanders. "He wrote that more people were probably killed by the fireworks than by Catherine's war against the Turks," said Mr Bompard.

He described the letters not as works of diplomatic politesse, but as being "intimate". He said: "In Voltaire's bedroom there was a portrait of Catherine in front of his bed."

Star of the North

Catherine II the Great was born Sophie Augusta Fredericka in 1729, a German princess who was sent to Russia in a diplomatic Prussian intrigue and grew more popular than the man she married, the Grand Duke Peter - later Peter III. After his death she became empress, extending the Russian empire south and westwards. She considered herself a philosopher, and the arts flourished. The Hermitage museum, St Petersburg, started as her collection. She corresponded with the great minds of her day, including Voltaire , who called her "the Star of the North".

  • Francois Marie Arouet de Voltaire

Most viewed

  • Front Matter
  • Table of Contents
  • Acknowledgments
  • Author’s Note
  • List of Abbreviations
  • Introduction:: Northern Racine or Russian Voltaire? Reconsidering Sumarokov’s Literary Models
  • The Poet as Critic:: Sumarokov and Voltairean Taste
  • The Poet as Philosophe
  • The Poet as Playwright-Philosophe
  • Appendix A:: Voltaire’s Letter to Sumarokov
  • Appendix B:: Preface to the Tragedy Dimitry the Pretender
  • Selected Bibliography
  • Back Matter

did voltaire ever visit russia

  • History Classics
  • Your Profile
  • Find History on Facebook (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on Twitter (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on YouTube (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on Instagram (Opens in a new window)
  • Find History on TikTok (Opens in a new window)
  • This Day In History
  • History Podcasts
  • History Vault

10 Things You Should Know About Voltaire

By: Evan Andrews

Updated: August 8, 2023 | Original: November 21, 2014

Portrait of Francois Marie Arouet called Voltaire (1694-1778) holding a copy of "The Henriade". Painting after Maurice Quentin Delatour called Quentin De La Tour or Quentin De Latour (1704-1788), 1728. 0,62 x 0,5 m. Castle Museum, Versailles, France (Photo by Leemage/Corbis via Getty Images)

1. The origins of his famous pen name are unclear.

Voltaire had a strained relationship with his father, who discouraged his literary aspirations and tried to force him into a legal career. Possibly to show his rejection of his father’s values, he dropped his family name and adopted the nom de plume “Voltaire” upon completing his first play in 1718.

Voltaire never explained the meaning of his pen name, so scholars can only speculate on its origins. The most popular theory maintains the name is an anagram of a certain Latinized spelling of “Arouet,” but others have claimed it was a reference to the name of a family chateau or a nod to the nickname “volontaire” (volunteer), which Voltaire may have been given as a sarcastic reference to his stubbornness.

2. He was imprisoned in the Bastille for nearly a year. 

Voltaire’s caustic wit first got him into trouble with the authorities in May 1716, when he was briefly exiled from Paris for composing poems mocking the French regent’s family. The young writer was unable to bite his tongue, however, and only a year later he was arrested and confined to the Bastille for writing scandalous verse implying the regent had an incestuous relationship with his daughter.

Voltaire boasted that his cell gave him some quiet time to think, and he eventually did 11 months behind bars before winning a release. He later endured another short stint in the Bastille in April 1726, when he was arrested for planning to duel an aristocrat that had insulted and beaten him. To escape further jail time, he voluntarily exiled himself to England, where he remained for nearly three years.

3. He became hugely wealthy by exploiting a flaw in the French lottery.

In 1729, Voltaire teamed with mathematician Charles Marie de La Condamine and others to exploit a lucrative loophole in the French national lottery. The government shelled out massive prizes for the contest each month, but an error in calculation meant that the payouts were larger than the value of all the tickets in circulation. With this in mind, Voltaire, La Condamine and a syndicate of other gamblers were able to repeatedly corner the market and rake in massive winnings.

The scheme left Voltaire with a windfall of nearly half a million francs, setting him up for life and allowing him to devote himself solely to his literary career.

4. He was an extraordinary prolific writer.

Voltaire wrote more than 50 plays, dozens of treatises on science, politics and philosophy, and several books of history on everything from the Russian Empire to the French Parliament. Along the way, he also managed to squeeze in heaps of verse and a voluminous correspondence amounting to some 20,000 letters to friends and contemporaries.

Voltaire supposedly kept up his prodigious output by spending up to 18 hours a day writing or dictating to secretaries, often while still in bed. He may have also been fueled by heroic amounts of caffeine—according to some sources, he drank as many as 40 cups a day.

5. Many of his most famous works were banned.

Since his writing denigrated everything from organized religion to the justice system, Voltaire ran up against frequent censorship from the French government. A good portion of his work was suppressed, and the authorities even ordered certain books to be burned by the state executioner.

To combat the censors, Voltaire had much of his output printed abroad, and he published under a veil of assumed names and pseudonyms. His famous novella “Candide” was originally attributed to a “Dr. Ralph,” and he actively tried to distance himself from it for several years after both the government and the church condemned it.

Despite his best attempts to remain anonymous, Voltaire lived in almost constant fear of arrest. He was forced to flee to the French countryside after his “Letters Concerning the English Nation” was released in 1734, and he went on to spend the majority of his later life in unofficial exile in Switzerland.

6. He helped popularize the famous tale about Sir Isaac Newton and the apple.

Though the two never met in person, Voltaire was an enthusiastic acolyte of the English physicist and mathematician Sir Isaac Newton. Upon receiving a copy of Newton’s “Principia Mathematica,” he claimed he knelt down before it in reverence, “as was only right.”

Voltaire played a key role in popularizing Newton’s ideas, and he offered one of the first accounts of how the famed scientist developed his theories on gravity. In his 1727 “Essay on Epic Poetry,” Voltaire wrote that Newton “had the first thought of his System of Gravitation, upon seeing an apple falling from a tree.”

Voltaire wasn’t the original source for the story of the “Eureka!” moment, as has often been claimed, but his account was instrumental in making it a fabled part of Newton’s biography.

7. He had a brief career as a spy for the French government.

Voltaire struck up a lively correspondence with Frederick the Great in the late 1730s, and he later made several journeys to meet the Prussian monarch in person. Before one of these visits in 1743, Voltaire concocted an ill-advised scheme to use his new position to repair his reputation with the French court. After hatching a deal to serve as a government informant, he wrote several letters to the French giving inside dope on Frederick’s foreign policy and finances.

Voltaire proved a lousy spy, however, and his plan quickly fell apart after Frederick grew suspicious of his motives. The two nevertheless remained close friends—some have even claimed they were lovers—and Voltaire later moved to Prussia in 1750 to take a permanent position in the Frederick’s court. Their relationship finally soured in 1752, after Voltaire made a series of scathing attacks on the head of the Prussian Academy of Sciences.

Frederick responded by lambasting Voltaire, and ordered that a satirical pamphlet he had written be publicly burned. Voltaire left the court for good in 1753, supposedly telling a friend, “I was enthusiastic about [Frederick] for 16 years, but he has cured me of this long illness.”

Illustration of Voltaire translating the work of Isaac Newton

8. He never married or fathered children.

While Voltaire technically died a bachelor, his personal life was a revolving door of mistresses, paramours and long-term lovers. He carried out a famous 16-year affair with the brilliant—and very married—author and scientist Émilie du Châtelet, and later had a committed, though secretive, partnership with his own niece, Marie-Louise Mignot. The two lived as a married couple from the early 1750s until his death, and they even adopted a child in 1760, when they took in a destitute young woman named Marie- Françoise Corneille. Voltaire later paid the dowry for Corneille’s marriage, and often referred to Mignot and himself as her “parents.”

9. He set up a successful watchmaking business in his old age.

While living in Ferney, France, in the 1770s, Voltaire joined with a group of Swiss horologists in starting a watchmaking business at his estate. With the septuagenarian Voltaire acting as manager and financier, the endeavor soon grew into a village-wide industry, and Ferney watches came to rival some of the best in Europe.

“Our watches are very well made,” he once wrote to the French ambassador to the Vatican, “very handsome, very good and cheap.”

Voltaire saw the enterprise as a way to prop up the Ferney economy, and he used his vast network of upper class contacts to find prospective buyers. Among others, he eventually succeeded in peddling his wares to the likes of Catherine the Great of Russia and King Louis XV of France.

10. He continued causing controversy even in death.

Voltaire died in Paris in 1778, just a few months after returning to the city for the first time in 28 years to oversee the production of one of his plays. Over the last few days of his life, Catholic Church officials repeatedly visited Voltaire—a lifelong deist who was often critical of organized religion—in the hope of persuading him to retract his opinions and make a deathbed confession. The great writer was unmoved, and supposedly brushed off the priests by saying, “let me die in peace.”

His refusal meant that he was officially denied a Christian burial, but his friends and family managed to arrange a secret interment in the Champagne region of France before the order became official.

did voltaire ever visit russia

Sign up for Inside History

Get HISTORY’s most fascinating stories delivered to your inbox three times a week.

By submitting your information, you agree to receive emails from HISTORY and A+E Networks. You can opt out at any time. You must be 16 years or older and a resident of the United States.

More details : Privacy Notice | Terms of Use | Contact Us

Home

Subscription Offers

Give a Gift

did voltaire ever visit russia

Voltaire and Peter the Great

‘The story of Charles XII,’ wrote Voltaire, ‘was entertaining; that of Peter instructive.’ A. Lentin describes a unique example of early modern Franco-Russian relations.

Voltaire’s interest in Peter the Great was first aroused in 1717, when, as a young man of twenty-two, he saw the Russian monarch strolling informally in the streets of Paris. ‘Neither he nor I,’ recalled Voltaire years later, ‘had any idea that I should one day be his historian.’

did voltaire ever visit russia

To continue reading this article you will need to purchase access to the online archive.

Buy Online Access    Buy Print & Archive Subscription

If you have already purchased access, or are a print & archive subscriber, please ensure you are  logged in .

Please email [email protected] if you have any problems.

Popular articles

Queen Mary being cheered by a crowd of workers at William Doxford & Sons Ltd, Sunderland, 15 June 1917. Tyne & Wear Archives & Museums. Public Domain.

When Did Britain’s Age of Deference End – and Why?

A scene from Auschwitz by Holocaust survivor Leo Haas, c. 1947. Center for Jewish History, New York. Public Domain.

Why Were the Jews Persecuted?

Voltaire/Aus Russlands Vergangenheit (Sketches From the Early History of Russia)/Hegel..

How Voltaire Went from Bastille Prisoner to Famous Playwright

Three hundred years ago this week, the French philosopher and writer began his career with a popular retelling of Sophocles’ ‘Oedipus’

Lorraine Boissoneault

Lorraine Boissoneault

Atelier_de_Nicolas_de_Largillière,_portrait_de_Voltaire,_détail_(musée_Carnavalet)_-002.jpg

François-Marie d’Arouet was the kind of precocious teen who always got invited to the best parties. Earning a reputation for his wit and catchy verses among the elites of 18th-century Paris, the young writer got himself exiled to the countryside in May 1716 for writing criticism of the ruling family. But Arouet—who would soon adopt the pen name “Voltaire”—was only getting started in his takedowns of those in power. In the coming years, those actions would have far more drastic repercussions: imprisonment for him, and a revolution for his country. And it all started with a story of incest.

In 1715, the young Arouet began a daunting new project: adapting the story of Oedipus for a contemporary French audience. The ancient Greek tale chronicles the downfall of Oedipus, who fulfilled a prophecy that he would kill his father, the king of Thebes, and marry his mother. Greek playwright Sophocles wrote the earliest version of the play in his tragedy, Oedipus Rex . As recently as 1659, the famed French dramatist Pierre Corneille had adapted the play, but Arouet thought the story deserved an update, and he happened to be living at the perfect time to give it one.

On September 1, 1715, Louis XIV (also known as the “Sun King”) died without leaving a clear successor. One of the most powerful rulers in the history of France, raising its fortunes and expanding colonial holdings, Louis also dragged the country into three major wars. He centralized power in France and elevated the Catholic Church by ruthlessly persecuting French Protestants. The king’s only son predeceased him, as did his grandson. His great-grandson, at age 5, needed a regent to oversee the ruling of the state. That duty fell to Philippe Duc d’Orléans, who used his position to essentially rule the country as Regent until his own death.

Philippe change the geopolitical trajectory of France, forming alliances with Austria, the Netherlands, and Great Britain. He also upended the old social order, opposing censorship and allowing once-banned books to be reprinted. The atmosphere “changed radically as the country came under the direction of a man who lived in the Palais-Royal, at the heart of Paris, and was widely known to indulge mightily in the pleasures of the table, the bottle, and the flesh—including, it was no less commonly believed, the flesh of his daughter, the duchesse de Berry,” writes Roger Pearson in Voltaire Almighty: A Life in Pursuit of Freedom .

For Arouet, the loosening of social restrictions created an almost limitless sense of possibilities, and harnessing theater was perhaps the most effective way to spread the message of freedom and tolerance to the public.

“Voltaire estimated that only five percent of the population in Europe could read in his Letters on England in 1733,” says Gail Noyer, the editor and translator of Voltaire’s Revolution: Writings From His Campaign to Free Laws From Religion . “So [public performances of] plays had far more influence than books did, until much later in the century.”

As for where his work would be performed, only one choice presented itself, even though Paris hosted multiple theaters. “The Comédie Française had a virtual monopoly as the only theatre authorized and supervised by the court for the staging of tragedies and serious dramas,” writes Ian Davidson in Voltaire: A Life . “Almost anybody who wanted to be a writer wanted to write for the Comédie Française.”

Arouet worked feverishly on his play, Oedipe , only for it to be rejected by the Comédie Française. Still, the theater didn’t give him an absolute dismissal, instead suggesting revisions, which he continued hacking away at for several years. Finally, on January 19, 1717, the theatre agreed to put on a revised form of the play.

But the timing for Arouet’s success couldn’t have been worse. While he’d been at work on his play, Arouet continued to write popular verses that were shared among his friends—including a piece that referenced the rumors of the Regent’s incestuous conduct with his daughter:

“It is not the son, it is the father;

It is the daughter, and not the mother;

So far, so good.

They have already made Eteocles;

If suddenly he loses his two eyes;

That would be a true story for Sophocles.”

The verse clearly pointed to the Regent , Philippe, and his relationship with his daughter, and even for the permissive ruler, it was a bridge too far. On May 16, 1717, Arouet was arrested and taken to the formidable Bastille. He tried to plead innocence in his case, claiming he wasn’t the one who’d written the verses, but he had already admitted authorship to several friends—friends who turned out to be spies. “Conditions in the Bastille were harsh and oppressive, with its ten-foot walls, its ‘triple locks, and grills and bolts and bars’, and with poor food and no sunlight,” Davidson writes . Even worse, Arouet had no idea when he might be set free, if ever. His case never went through any type of judicial process; the length of his detention depended solely on the whim of the Regent.

After 11 months, the Regency decided to show mercy to Arouet, releasing him on Holy Thursday, April 14, 1718. Arouet was placed on the 18th-century equivalent of house arrest for several more months, but was finally allowed free entry in and out of Paris, and on November 18, 1718, the young man who had started to address himself as “Voltaire” had the first major success of his life: the staging of Oedipe at the Comédie Française.

The play was immensely popular, going on to run for a nearly unprecedented 32 performances, Davidson writes. Perhaps some of that popularity stemmed from the Regent’s titillating scandals. But Voltaire didn’t just attack hereditary monarchy; he also leveled charges against the corrupt power of the Church. In one of the playwright’s most famous lines, Queen Jocasta says , “Our priests are not what the foolish people imagine; their wisdom is based solely on our credulity.” Considering how powerful the Catholic Church remained, it was a dangerous dig to make—but one audiences thrilled to hear.

“Generally, the moral content of earlier plays stressed love of God and king, patriotic duty and the like,” writes literary historian Marcus Allen . “In the hands of Voltaire, however, the play itself became the primary vehicle for launching attacks upon the evils of the ancien régime.”

The popularity of the play catapulted Voltaire to true fame, but it also taught him of the dangers that accompanied outspokenness. As he continued writing plays, poems, letters and stories, Voltaire faced an increasing number of critics as well as fans, and would be exiled from France multiple times over the course of his life for offending the Catholic Church and the monarchy. But Voltaire’s stays in England, Holland, Belgium and Prussia exposed him to some of the era’s greatest Enlightenment figures; he was the first to bring the writings of Isaac Newton and philosopher John Locke to France. With his condemnation of torture, war, religious persecution and absolute monarchy, Voltaire paved the way for the ideas that would fuel the French Revolution in 1789, and inspired great American intellects like Benjamin Franklin and Thomas Jefferson. Yet according to Noyer, much of that legacy is forgotten today.

“The only thing people seem to know anymore is Candide,” Noyer says, referencing a satirical novel about the dangers of optimism. “I think it’s only chosen as a safe subject, because it certainly wasn’t a big deal in his lifetime.” For Noyer, the real masterpiece is how much Voltaire managed to achieve with his words: helping to inspire the French Revolution and teaching people to think more critically about religious intolerance and injustice.

Get the latest History stories in your inbox?

Click to visit our Privacy Statement .

Lorraine Boissoneault

Lorraine Boissoneault | | READ MORE

Lorraine Boissoneault is a contributing writer to SmithsonianMag.com covering history and archaeology. She has previously written for The Atlantic, Salon, Nautilus and others. She is also the author of The Last Voyageurs: Retracing La Salle's Journey Across America. Website: http://www.lboissoneault.com/

  • Cast & crew
  • User reviews

Back to Black

Marisa Abela in Back to Black (2024)

The life and music of Amy Winehouse, through the journey of adolescence to adulthood and the creation of one of the best-selling albums of our time. The life and music of Amy Winehouse, through the journey of adolescence to adulthood and the creation of one of the best-selling albums of our time. The life and music of Amy Winehouse, through the journey of adolescence to adulthood and the creation of one of the best-selling albums of our time.

  • Sam Taylor-Johnson
  • Matt Greenhalgh
  • Marisa Abela
  • Eddie Marsan
  • Jack O'Connell
  • 67 User reviews
  • 74 Critic reviews
  • 49 Metascore

Official Trailer

  • Nick Shymansky

Pete Lee-Wilson

  • Perfume Paul
  • Great Auntie Renee

Michael S. Siegel

  • Uncle Harold
  • Auntie Melody

Anna Darvas

  • All cast & crew
  • Production, box office & more at IMDbPro

The Big List of Summer Movies

Production art

More like this

Amy Winehouse

Did you know

  • Trivia Marisa Abela had done most of the singing in this film herself. She trained extensively to mimic Amy Winehouse 's vocals.

Technical specs

  • Runtime 2 hours 2 minutes

Related news

Contribute to this page.

Marisa Abela in Back to Black (2024)

  • See more gaps
  • Learn more about contributing

More to explore

Production art

Recently viewed

Ukraine-Russia war latest: Russian fighter-bomber 'shot down over Donetsk'; Ukraine faces another wave of Russian drones

A Russian Su-25 fighter-bomber jet has been shot down over the eastern region of Donetsk, according to Volodymyr Zelenskyy. Elsewhere, Ukraine's air force said it downed 23 out of 24 Russian drones overnight.

Sunday 5 May 2024 15:20, UK

Please use Chrome browser for a more accessible video player

  • Russia claims complete control over another village  
  • Analysis: Ukraine looks to trade territory for time
  • Ukraine retreating in attempt to avoid being outflanked, ISW says
  • Russian fighter-bomber 'downed by Ukraine'
  • Moscow lashes out at Baltic states
  • Analysis:  UN undermined as North Korea appears to defy arms embargo
  • Analysis: Will US aid help turn tide on Russia?
  • Your questions answered:  Why can't Ukraine destroy key Crimean bridge?
  • Listen to the Sky News Daily above and  tap here  to follow wherever you get your podcasts

We're pausing our live coverage of the war in Ukraine for the time being - thanks for tuning in. 

This footage shows Russian troops preparing for a Victory Day parade in the Red Square in Moscow. 

The event comes just days after Vladimir Putin's fifth inauguration as president of Russia. 

By  Sean Bell , military analyst 

President Volodymyr Zelenskyy has claimed that Ukrainian forces shot down a Russian Su-25 fighter-bomber jet over the Donetsk region yesterday.   

The Russian fighter - codenamed Frogfoot by NATO - is primarily used to provide close air support for Russian frontline troops. 

Pre-war the Russians had between 70 and 80 serviceable Su-25s, but Ukraine claims to have shot down around six of these to date.

But is this loss important in the broader scheme of the war?

Fresh Western supplies of weapons are starting to arrive in Ukraine, and the expectation is that air defence missiles would probably be the first priority. 

Ukraine's claim that it has shot down 23 of 24 Russian drones last night and the successful targeting of one of its fighter jets also suggests that Ukraine is stabilising its defensive posture.  

However, on the frontline, reports suggest that Russian forces have made further advances, taking several more communities - including Ocheretyne.  

Military experts believe that Ukraine is making a "managed withdrawal" from key sites to trade territory for time - in anticipation of the arrival of fresh supplies of Western military aid.

Military offensives generally incur significantly greater losses for the attacking force than that defending. 

The UK's Ministry of Defence has reported that Russia's April offensive action has resulted in 899 Russian casualties per day, which is higher than at the peak of the attritional battle for Bakhmut. 

However, it has proven very difficult to secure reliable figures for the Ukraine war, with Russia playing down the scale of its losses, and Kyiv avoiding reporting specific numbers.

Regardless, it seems likely that Vladimir Putin will be keen to avoid another round of Russian mobilisation for fear of highlighting the growing numbers of Russian casualties.  

Instead,  Russia is reported to be recruiting foreign nationals to bolster its army, with the latest target being Cuba.  

It is reported that Cuban recruits have been offered monthly salaries of up to £1600 per month, when their average salary in Cuba is around £20 per month. 

The package naturally appears attractive, particularly if recruits are initially told that they will not serve on the frontline.

Until the resupply of Western weapons and ammunition arrives, it looks likely that Russia will continue to capitalise on Ukraine's shortage of weapons to push forward and secure as much territory as possible in the Donbas.  

And Ukraine will seek to ensure Russia pays a high price for every metre of ground ceded.  

These images show members of the 93rd Kholodnyi war separate mechanised brigade celebrating Orthodox Easter on the frontlines of Russia's war against Ukraine. 

The Ukrainian troops are fighting in Donetsk, where much of Russia's military focus is. 

This footage shows firefighters battling a blaze in Kharkiv in the early hours of yesterday morning. 

The region was consistently targeted yesterday, with several drone and shelling attacks across the area.

Russia's targeting of Ukrainian energy infrastructure with drones and missiles has cost Kyiv some £1bn (£796m), the country's energy minister has claimed. 

German Galushchenko said that, since mid-March, Russian forces have been attacking Ukrainian thermal and hydropower stations - as well as main networks - on an almost daily basis.

This has led to blackouts in many regions.

"Today, we are talking about the amounts of losses for more than a billion dollars," he said.

"But the attacks continue, and it is obvious that the losses will grow," he added. 

By Sean Bell , military analyst 

The United Nations Security Council (UNSC) has adopted nine major sanctions on North Korea in response to the country's nuclear and missile activities since 2006.  

In June of that year, the UNSC established an embargo on exports of major arms to and imports from North Korea. 

In June 2009, it widened the embargo to all arms, except for the export small arms and light weapons to the country, before eventually banning those too in 2015.

Russia was a signatory to those embargoes.

Yet, late last year, a series of Russian senior leadership visits to North Korea were focused on solving Russia's growing demand for weapons, artillery shells and missiles to support its war in Ukraine.  

Although Russia has denied that it imports North Korean weapons, the Royal United Service Institute (RUSI) has been tracking ships transporting weapons to Russia.  

It has tracked four Russian cargo ships, each transporting hundreds of containers.

Estimates suggest that over 7,000 containers carrying over one million ammunition shells, rockets and missiles have been sold to Russia by North Korea since a deal was struck last year.

Russia denies that it is importing any North Korean weapons.

However, an inspector from the Conflict Arms Research team based in Ukraine has been studying the remains of a series of missiles fired at Ukrainian targets this year and has made a series of important discoveries.  

According to reports, parts of the missile remains included characters only used in the Korean alphabet, and the number '112' was stamped into parts of the missile - '2023' in the Korean calendar.

Closer investigation of hundreds of electronic components revealed that the missiles were "bursting" with Western technology.  

Most of the electronics were manufactured in the US or Europe, and were sourced over the past few years.  

Despite supposedly significant sanctions, North Korea has managed to illicitly procure large quantities of Western technology, assemble missiles and sell them to Russia to be used in its war in Ukraine.

Although the North Korean weapons might not be very effective, they are cheap, so can be procured in large quantities and used to degrade Ukrainian air defence systems.

Quantity has a quality all of its own - so what is the point of sanctions if they can so easily be bypassed?  

North Korea is evidently profiting from its arms export arrangement with Russia, which will create further opportunities for Pyongyang to expand arms exports as a vital source of revenue - to grow its economy and military capability.  

Not to mention it undermines the authority of the UN - given that Russia is a signatory to the ban on North Korean arms exports, yet is flagrantly ignoring this ban to meet its wartime needs.

Yet, the UN appears powerless to enforce its own sanctions.

Russia claims it has taken complete control of the village of Ocheretyne in eastern Ukraine. 

The village, which lies northwest of the former Ukrainian stronghold of Avdiivka, which Russia captured in February, had a pre-war population of around 3,000. 

Russia has made steady advances since taking Avdiivka, and this would mark the latest in a string of villages in the area to fall into Moscow's grasp. 

These images show Russian servicemen and women preparing for the annual Victory Day parade in Moscow. 

On the 9 May, the military will march through the Red Square in front of Vladimir Putin - who will have been sworn in once again as president days earlier (see 9.04am post).

The parade will showcase Russian military hardware with vehicles, aircraft and soldiers all taking the stage.

Russian forces are continuing to advance west of Avdiivka, according to the Institute for the Study of War (ISW).

The US-based thinktank said it had geolocated footage showing Russian soldiers advancing near Arkhanhelske, which is just northwest of the Russian-held city. 

Fighting has intensified in villages like Arkhanhelske near Avdiivka, and further north around Chasiv Yar in recent weeks. 

"ISW assesses that the Russian seizure of Arkhanhelske also indicates that Russian forces likely control Keramik and Novokalynove (both southeast of Arkhanhelske)," it said. 

It also said it had noted Ukrainian forces withdrawing from northern Arkhanhelske. 

"Ukrainian forces may have decided to trade space for time as they wait for the arrival of US aid to the frontline at scale in the coming weeks - an appropriate decision for an under-resourced force at risk of being outflanked," it said. 

"Russian forces appear to be choosing to exploit the tactical situation northwest of Avdiivka - a sound military undertaking - but their ultimate objective in this frontline sector remains unclear."

Here's the latest battlefield situation on the ground...

Be the first to get Breaking News

Install the Sky News app for free

did voltaire ever visit russia

IMAGES

  1. Voltaire en San Petersburgo

    did voltaire ever visit russia

  2. Voltaire en San Petersburgo

    did voltaire ever visit russia

  3. Voltaire Biography

    did voltaire ever visit russia

  4. The Statue of Voltaire in the Hermitage in St. Petersburg.Russia

    did voltaire ever visit russia

  5. Voltaire

    did voltaire ever visit russia

  6. Voltaire the Freethinker Who Fought for Everybody's Freedom

    did voltaire ever visit russia

VIDEO

  1. Леонид Кацва. Москва и Вильно: два русских пути. Лекция 5

  2. Альберт Валиев: Горный поход по Памиру и самостоятельное восхождение на пик Ленина

  3. Aurelio Voltaire

  4. ⁴ᴷ THE FIRST DAYS OF SUMMER IN RUSSIA 🇷🇺 Walking tour in the Catherine Park

  5. Радищев

  6. Николай Злобин в «Библио-Глобусе». «Русский вираж. Куда идет Россия?»

COMMENTS

  1. Voltaire and Russia in the Age of Enlightenment

    Voltaire's long interest in Russia was probably stimulated during his research for the Histoire de Charles XII. His ties to Russia became even closer in 1746, during the reign of Elizabeth, daughter of Peter the Great, when he was made an honorable member of the Russian Academy of Sciences and appointed a Historiographer of the Russian Empire. ...

  2. Voltaire

    The town of Ferney, where Voltaire lived out the last 20 years of his life, was officially named Ferney-Voltaire in honor of its most famous resident, in 1878. [271] His château is a museum. Voltaire's library is preserved intact in the National Library of Russia at Saint Petersburg.

  3. Russian Enlightenment

    Mikeshin's Monument to Catherine the Great after the Alexandrine Theatre in St. Petersburg. The Russian Age of Enlightenment was a period in the 18th century in which the government began to actively encourage the proliferation of arts and sciences, which had a profound impact on Russian culture. During this time, the first Russian university was founded, a library, a theatre, a public museum ...

  4. Voltaire's Russia

    I. France and Russia, 1700-1750 II. Voltaire, historian of Russia: i. The background III. Voltaire, historian of Russia: ii. the concepts IV. Voltaire's personal contacts with Russia V. Voltaire and Catherine the Great VI. Russia: fact, fiction and formulae VII. The debate: Voltaire versus Rousseau VIII. The debate: philosophes, westernizers ...

  5. 'If I Were Younger I Would Make Myself Russian': Voltaire's Encounter

    Voltaire was not altogether unintimidated by the unforeseen success of Russia, of an empire "more vast than all the rest of Europe, than the Roman empire ever was, or that which Alexander ...

  6. Voltaire

    Voltaire (1694-1778) was a French author, historian, and philosopher whose thoughts on religious toleration and moderation of authoritarian power were influential during the Enlightenment.His most famous work today is the satirical Candide, which presents Voltaire's critical thoughts on other philosophers, the Catholic Church, and the French state in order to highlight the need for real ...

  7. Voltaire and Russia in the Age of Enlightenment

    Voltaire's long interest in Russia was probably stimulated during his research for the Histoire de Charles XII. His ties to Russia became even closer in 1746, during the reign of Elizabeth ...

  8. Voltaire

    Voltaire's object was to show humanity slowly developing beyond barbarism. He supplemented these two works with one on Russian history during the reign of Peter the Great, Histoire de l'empire de Russie sous Pierre le Grand (1759-63), the Philosophie de l'histoire (1765), and the Précis du siècle de Louis XV (1768).

  9. Voltaire and Russia in the Age of Enlightenment

    Voltaire's long interest in Russia was probably stimulated during his research for the Histoire de Charles XII. His ties to Russia became even closer in 1746, during the reign of Elizabeth, daughter of Peter the Great, when he was made an honorable member of the Russian Academy of Sciences and appointed a Historiographer of the Russian Empire. ...

  10. Voltaire's Russia

    Abstract: Introduction I. France and Russia, 1700-1750 II. Voltaire, historian of Russia: i. The background III. Voltaire, historian of Russia: ii. the concepts IV. Voltaire's personal contacts with Russia V. Voltaire and Catherine the great VI. Russia: fact, fiction and formulae VII. The debate: Voltaire versus Rousseau VIII. The debate: philosophes, westernizers and Slavophiles Conclusion ...

  11. Voltaire (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)

    Voltaire. François-Marie d'Arouet (1694-1778), better known by his pen name Voltaire, was a French writer and public activist who played a singular role in defining the eighteenth-century movement called the Enlightenment. At the center of his work was a new conception of philosophy and the philosopher that in several crucial respects ...

  12. How Voltaire praised the 'enlightened despot' Catherine the Great

    The most telling comments in the letter for today's Russia refer to Catherine's governing style. Mr Bompard said Voltaire, who lambasted the French monarchy during the Enlightenment for its ...

  13. A Voltaire for Russia: A. P. Sumarokov's Journey from Poet-Critic to

    In A Voltaire for Russia, Amanda Ewington examines the tumultuous literary career of Alexander Petrovich Sumarokov in relation to that of his slightly older French contemporary, Voltaire. Although largely unknown in the English-speaking world, Sumarokov was one of the founding fathers of modern Russian literature, renowned in his own time as a ...

  14. Connections Between Voltaire and Rousseau: Themes of the ...

    Following Voltaire's death, part of his library was purchased by the Russian empress, Catherine the Great, and in most of Voltaire's books, "especially works by Jean Jacques Rousseau, and in ...

  15. 10 Things You Should Know About Voltaire

    Voltaire supposedly kept up his prodigious output by spending up to 18 hours a day writing or dictating to secretaries, often while still in bed. He may have also been fueled by heroic amounts of ...

  16. Voltaire and Peter the Great

    A. Lentin | Published in History Today Volume 18 Issue 10 October 1968. Voltaire's interest in Peter the Great was first aroused in 1717, when, as a young man of twenty-two, he saw the Russian monarch strolling informally in the streets of Paris. 'Neither he nor I,' recalled Voltaire years later, 'had any idea that I should one day be ...

  17. Voltaire/Aus Russlands Vergangenheit (Sketches From the Early History

    Voltaire/Aus Russlands Vergangenheit (Sketches From the Early History of Russia)/Hegel.. ... will say : " A Russian is a Tartar, and a Tartar is an inferior being of medium height, a broad face ...

  18. Voltaire and Rousseau: irreconcilable contradiction

    The manuscripts held by the National Library of Russia comprise of over 1400 private archives and collections that today number more than 450 000 valuable items for all periods and countries. ... Until the end of his life, Rousseau did not believe in the authorship of Voltaire and misattributed the pamphlet to the Geneva pastor Jacob Vernes ...

  19. How Voltaire Went from Bastille Prisoner to Famous Playwright

    But Arouet—who would soon adopt the pen name "Voltaire"—was only getting started in his takedowns of those in power. In the coming years, those actions would have far more drastic ...

  20. Voltaire and Rousseau: The Social Contract

    The Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right is Rousseau's main work dealing with political issues, in which he substantiates the principle of sovereignty of the people. On the pages of this book, Voltaire left numerous marginalia, arguing with the author. The first chapter of The Social Contract opens with the famous sentence: "Man is ...

  21. Voltaire

    Voltaire - Enlightenment, Philosophy, Satire: During a stay that lasted more than two years he succeeded in learning the English language; he wrote his notebooks in English and to the end of his life he was able to speak and write it fluently. He met such English men of letters as Alexander Pope, Jonathan Swift, and William Congreve, the philosopher George Berkeley, and Samuel Clarke, the ...

  22. Voltaire's Struggle for Religious Tolerance. Online Exhibition of the

    Voltaire never advocated the separation between church and state in the modern sense. This principle was one of the legacies of the French revolution of the end of the 18th century. The thinker believed that the state should establish one state religion, the rest are only permissible. However, firstly, governmental power should have the ...

  23. State visit by Elizabeth II to Russia

    Queen Elizabeth II of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland, her husband Prince Philip, Duke of Edinburgh and Foreign Secretary Douglas Hurd made a state visit to Russia from 17 to 20 October 1994, hosted by the President of Russia, Boris Yeltsin.It is the first and so far only visit by a reigning British monarch on Russian soil.. The four-day visit is said to be one of the ...

  24. Back to Black (2024)

    Back to Black: Directed by Sam Taylor-Johnson. With Marisa Abela, Jack O'Connell, Eddie Marsan, Lesley Manville. The life and music of Amy Winehouse, through the journey of adolescence to adulthood and the creation of one of the best-selling albums of our time.

  25. Ukraine-Russia war latest: Russian fighter-bomber 'shot down over

    A Russian Su-25 fighter-bomber jet has been shot down over the eastern region of Donetsk, according to Volodymyr Zelenskyy. Elsewhere, Ukraine's air force said it downed 23 out of 24 Russian ...