Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • View all journals
  • Explore content
  • About the journal
  • Publish with us
  • Sign up for alerts
  • Review Article
  • Published: 22 September 2016

Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework

  • Kalina Christoff 1 , 2 ,
  • Zachary C. Irving 3 ,
  • Kieran C. R. Fox 1 ,
  • R. Nathan Spreng 4 , 5 &
  • Jessica R. Andrews-Hanna 6  

Nature Reviews Neuroscience volume  17 ,  pages 718–731 ( 2016 ) Cite this article

25k Accesses

673 Citations

493 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Cognitive control
  • Schizophrenia

In the past 15 years, mind-wandering has become a prominent topic in cognitive neuroscience and psychology. Whereas mind-wandering has come to be predominantly defined as task-unrelated and/or stimulus-unrelated thought, we argue that this content-based definition fails to capture the defining quality of mind-wandering: the relatively free and spontaneous arising of mental states as the mind wanders.

We define spontaneous thought as a mental state, or a sequence of mental states, that arises relatively freely due to an absence of strong constraints on the contents of each state and on the transitions from one mental state to another. We propose that there are two general ways in which the content of mental states, and the transitions between them, can be constrained.

Deliberate and automatic constraints serve to limit the contents of thought and how these contents change over time. Deliberate constraints are implemented through cognitive control, whereas automatic constraints can be considered as a family of mechanisms that operate outside of cognitive control, including sensory or affective salience.

Within our framework, mind-wandering can be defined as a special case of spontaneous thought that tends to be more deliberately constrained than dreaming, but less deliberately constrained than creative thinking and goal-directed thought. In addition, mind-wandering can be clearly distinguished from rumination and other types of thought that are marked by a high degree of automatic constraints, such as obsessive thought.

In general, deliberate constraints are minimal during dreaming, tend to increase somewhat during mind-wandering, increase further during creative thinking and are strongest during goal-directed thought. There is a range of low-to-medium level of automatic constraints that can occur during dreaming, mind-wandering and creative thinking, but thought ceases to be spontaneous at the strongest levels of automatic constraint, such as during rumination or obsessive thought.

We propose a neural model of the interactions among sources of variability, automatic constraints and deliberate constraints on thought: the default network (DN) subsystem centred around the medial temporal lobe (MTL) (DN MTL ) and sensorimotor areas can act as sources of variability; the salience networks, the dorsal attention network (DAN) and the core DN subsystem (DN CORE ) can exert automatic constraints on the output of the DN MTL and sensorimotor areas, thus limiting the variability of thought; and the frontoparietal control network can exert deliberate constraints on thought by flexibly coupling with the DN CORE , the DAN or the salience networks, thus reinforcing or reducing the automatic constraints being exerted by the DN CORE , the DAN or the salience networks.

Most research on mind-wandering has characterized it as a mental state with contents that are task unrelated or stimulus independent. However, the dynamics of mind-wandering — how mental states change over time — have remained largely neglected. Here, we introduce a dynamic framework for understanding mind-wandering and its relationship to the recruitment of large-scale brain networks. We propose that mind-wandering is best understood as a member of a family of spontaneous-thought phenomena that also includes creative thought and dreaming. This dynamic framework can shed new light on mental disorders that are marked by alterations in spontaneous thought, including depression, anxiety and attention deficit hyperactivity disorder.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Access options

Subscribe to this journal

Receive 12 print issues and online access

176,64 € per year

only 14,72 € per issue

Rent or buy this article

Prices vary by article type

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

mind wandering significato

Similar content being viewed by others

mind wandering significato

Recent advances in the neuroscience of spontaneous and off-task thought: implications for mental health

Aaron Kucyi, Julia W. Y. Kam, … Susan Whitfield-Gabrieli

mind wandering significato

Introspective and Neurophysiological Measures of Mind Wandering in Schizophrenia

S. Iglesias-Parro, M. F. Soriano, … A. J. Ibáñez-Molina

mind wandering significato

Prediction of stimulus-independent and task-unrelated thought from functional brain networks

Aaron Kucyi, Michael Esterman, … Susan Whitfield-Gabrieli

James, W. The Principles of Psychology (Henry Holt and Company, 1890).

Google Scholar  

Callard, F., Smallwood, J., Golchert, J. & Margulies, D. S. The era of the wandering mind? Twenty-first century research on self-generated mental activity. Front. Psychol. 4 , 891 (2013).

PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Andreasen, N. C. et al. Remembering the past: two facets of episodic memory explored with positron emission tomography. Am. J. Psychiatry 152 , 1576–1585 (1995).

CAS   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Binder, J. R., Frost, J. A. & Hammeke, T. A. Conceptual processing during the conscious resting state: a functional MRI study. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 11 , 80–93 (1999).

Stark, C. E. & Squire, L. R. When zero is not zero: the problem of ambiguous baseline conditions in fMRI. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 98 , 12760–12766 (2001).

CAS   PubMed   PubMed Central   Google Scholar  

Christoff, K. & Gabrieli, J. D. E. The frontopolar cortex and human cognition: evidence for a rostrocaudal hierarchical organization within the human prefrontal cortex. Psychobiology 28 , 168–186 (2000).

Shulman, G. L. et al. Common blood flow changes across visual tasks: II. Decreases cerebral cortex. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 9 , 648–663 (1997). This meta-analysis provides convincing evidence that a set of specific brain regions, which later became known as the default mode network, becomes consistently activated during rest.

Raichle, M. E. et al. A default mode of brain function. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 98 , 676–682 (2001). This highly influential theoretical paper coined the term 'default mode' to refer to cognitive and neural processes that occur in the absence of external task demands.

Singer, J. L. Daydreaming: An Introduction to the Experimental Study of Inner Experience (Random House, 1966).

Antrobus, J. S. Information theory and stimulus-independent thought. Br. J. Psychol. 59 , 423–430 (1968).

Antrobus, J. S., Singer, J. L., Goldstein, S. & Fortgang, M. Mind wandering and cognitive structure. Trans. NY Acad. Sci. 32 , 242–252 (1970).

CAS   Google Scholar  

Filler, M. S. & Giambra, L. M. Daydreaming as a function of cueing and task difficulty. Percept. Mot. Skills 37 , 503–509 (1973).

Giambra, L. M. Adult male daydreaming across the life span: a replication, further analyses, and tentative norms based upon retrospective reports. Int. J. Aging Hum. Dev. 8 , 197–228 (1977).

PubMed   Google Scholar  

Giambra, L. M. Sex differences in daydreaming and related mental activity from the late teens to the early nineties. Int. J. Aging Hum. Dev. 10 , 1–34 (1979).

Klinger, E. & Cox, W. M. Dimensions of thought flow in everyday life. Imagin. Cogn. Pers. 7 , 105–128 (1987). This is probably the earliest experience sampling study of mind-wandering in daily life, revealing that adults spend approximately one-third of their waking life engaged in undirected thinking.

Giambra, L. M. Task-unrelated-thought frequency as a function of age: a laboratory study. Psychol. Aging 4 , 136–143 (1989).

Teasdale, J. D., Proctor, L., Lloyd, C. A. & Baddeley, A. D. Working memory and stimulus-independent thought: effects of memory load and presentation rate. Eur. J. Cogn. Psychol. 5 , 417–433 (1993).

Giambra, L. M. A laboratory method for investigating influences on switching attention to task-unrelated imagery and thought. Conscious. Cogn. 4 , 1–21 (1995).

Klinger, E. Structure and Functions of Fantasy (John Wiley & Sons, 1971). This pioneering book summarizes the early empirical research on daydreaming and introduces important theoretical hypotheses, including the idea that task-unrelated thoughts are often about 'current concerns'.

Smallwood, J. & Schooler, J. W. The restless mind. Psychol. Bull. 132 , 946–958 (2006). This paper put mind-wandering in the forefront of psychological research, advancing the influential hypothesis that executive resources support mind-wandering.

Killingsworth, M. A. & Gilbert, D. T. A wandering mind is an unhappy mind. Science 330 , 932 (2010).

Mason, M. F. et al. Wandering minds: the default network and stimulus-independent thought. Science 315 , 393–395 (2007). This influential paper brought mind-wandering to the forefront of neuroscientific research, arguing for a link between DN recruitment and stimulus-independent thought.

Christoff, K., Gordon, A. M., Smallwood, J., Smith, R. & Schooler, J. W. Experience sampling during fMRI reveals default network and executive system contributions to mind wandering. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 106 , 8719–8724 (2009). This paper is the first to use online experience sampling to examine the neural correlates of mind-wandering and the first to find joint activation of the DN and executive network during this phenomenon.

Callard, F., Smallwood, J. & Margulies, D. S. Default positions: how neuroscience's historical legacy has hampered investigation of the resting mind. Front. Psychol. 3 , 321 (2012).

Smallwood, J. & Schooler, J. W. The science of mind wandering: empirically navigating the stream of consciousness. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 66 , 487–518 (2015). This comprehensive review synthesizes the recent research characterizing mind-wandering as task-unrelated and/or stimulus-independent thought.

Christoff, K. Undirected thought: neural determinants and correlates. Brain Res. 1428 , 51–59 (2012). This review disambiguates between different definitions of spontaneous thought and mind-wandering, and it argues that current definitions do not capture the dynamics of thought.

Irving, Z. C. Mind-wandering is unguided attention: accounting for the 'purposeful' wanderer. Philos. Stud. 173 , 547–571 (2016). This is one of the first philosophical theories of mind-wandering; this paper defines mind-wandering as unguided attention to explain why its dynamics contrast with automatically and deliberately guided forms of attention such as rumination and goal-directed thinking.

Carruthers, P. The Centered Mind: What the Science of Working Memory Shows Us About the Nature of Human Thought (Oxford Univ. Press, 2015).

Simpson, J. A. The Oxford English Dictionary (Clarendon Press, 1989).

Kane, M. J. et al. For whom the mind wanders, and when: an experience-sampling study of working memory and executive control in daily life. Psychol. Sci. 18 , 614–621 (2007). This study of mind-wandering in everyday life is one of the most important investigations into the complex relationship between mind-wandering and executive control.

Baird, B., Smallwood, J. & Schooler, J. W. Back to the future: autobiographical planning and the functionality of mind-wandering. Conscious. Cogn. 20 , 1604–1611 (2011).

Morsella, E., Ben-Zeev, A., Lanska, M. & Bargh, J. A. The spontaneous thoughts of the night: how future tasks breed intrusive cognitions. Social Cogn. 28 , 641–650 (2010).

Miller, E. K. & Cohen, J. D. An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 24 , 167–202 (2001).

Miller, E. K. The prefrontal cortex and cognitive control. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 1 , 59–65 (2000).

Markovic, J., Anderson, A. K. & Todd, R. M. Tuning to the significant: neural and genetic processes underlying affective enhancement of visual perception and memory. Behav. Brain Res. 259 , 229–241 (2014).

Todd, R. M., Cunningham, W. A., Anderson, A. K. & Thompson, E. Affect-biased attention as emotion regulation. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16 , 365–372 (2012).

Pessoa, L. The Cognitive-Emotional Brain: From Interactions to Integration (MIT Press, 2013).

Jonides, J. & Yantis, S. Uniqueness of abrupt visual onset in capturing attention. Percept. Psychophys. 43 , 346–354 (1988).

Christoff, K., Gordon, A. M. & Smith, R. in Neuroscience of Decision Making (eds Vartanian, O. & Mandel, D. R.) 259–284 (Psychology Press, 2011).

Stawarczyk, D., Majerus, S., Maj, M., Van der Linden, M. & D'Argembeau, A. Mind-wandering: phenomenology and function as assessed with a novel experience sampling method. Acta Psychol. (Amst.) 136 , 370–381 (2011).

Spreng, R. N., Mar, R. A. & Kim, A. S. N. The common neural basis of autobiographical memory, prospection, navigation, theory of mind, and the default mode: a quantitative meta-analysis. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 21 , 489–510 (2009). This paper provides some of the first quantitative evidence that the DN is associated with multiple cognitive functions.

Andrews-Hanna, J. R. The brain's default network and its adaptive role in internal mentation. Neuroscientist 18 , 251–270 (2012). This recent review describes a large-scale functional meta-analysis on the cognitive functions, functional subdivisions and clinical dysfunction of the DN.

Buckner, R. L. & Carroll, D. C. Self-projection and the brain. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11 , 49–57 (2007).

Buckner, R. L., Andrews-Hanna, J. R. & Schacter, D. L. The brain's default network: anatomy, function, and relevance to disease. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1124 , 1–38 (2008). This comprehensive review bridges across neuroscience, psychology and clinical research, and introduces a prominent hypothesis — the 'internal mentation hypothesis' — that the DN has an important role in spontaneous and directed forms of internal mentation.

Andrews-Hanna, J. R., Reidler, J. S., Sepulcre, J., Poulin, R. & Buckner, R. L. Functional-anatomic fractionation of the brain's default network. Neuron 65 , 550–562 (2010).

Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R. & Buckner, R. L. Remembering the past to imagine the future: the prospective brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 8 , 657–661 (2007).

Andrews-Hanna, J. R., Smallwood, J. & Spreng, R. N. The default network and self-generated thought: component processes, dynamic control, and clinical relevance. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1316 , 29–52 (2014).

Corbetta, M., Patel, G. & Shulman, G. L. The reorienting system of the human brain: from environment to theory of mind. Neuron 58 , 306–324 (2008). This paper outlines an influential theoretical framework that extends an earlier model by Corbetta and Shulman that drew a crucial distinction between the DAN and VAN.

Vanhaudenhuyse, A. et al. Two distinct neuronal networks mediate the awareness of environment and of self. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 23 , 570–578 (2011).

Smallwood, J. Distinguishing how from why the mind wanders: a process–occurrence framework for self-generated mental activity. Psychol. Bull. 139 , 519–535 (2013). This theoretical paper presents an important distinction between the events that determine when an experience initially occurs from the processes that sustain an experience over time.

Toro, R., Fox, P. T. & Paus, T. Functional coactivation map of the human brain. Cereb. Cortex 18 , 2553–2559 (2008).

Fox, M. D. et al. The human brain is intrinsically organized into dynamic, anticorrelated functional networks. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 102 , 9673–9678 (2005). This paper provides a unique insight into the functional antagonism between the default and dorsal attention systems.

CAS   PubMed Central   PubMed   Google Scholar  

Keller, C. J. et al. Neurophysiological investigation of spontaneous correlated and anticorrelated fluctuations of the BOLD signal. J. Neurosci. 33 , 6333–6342 (2013).

Seeley, W. W. et al. Dissociable intrinsic connectivity networks for salience processing and executive control. J. Neurosci. 27 , 2349–2356 (2007). This paper is the first to name the salience network and characterize its functional neuroanatomy.

Kucyi, A., Hodaie, M. & Davis, K. D. Lateralization in intrinsic functional connectivity of the temporoparietal junction with salience- and attention-related brain networks. J. Neurophysiol. 108 , 3382–3392 (2012).

Power, J. D. et al. Functional network organization of the human brain. Neuron 72 , 665–678 (2011).

Cole, M. W. et al. Multi-task connectivity reveals flexible hubs for adaptive task control. Nat. Neurosci. 16 , 1348–1355 (2013).

Vincent, J. L., Kahn, I., Snyder, A. Z., Raichle, M. E. & Buckner, R. L. Evidence for a frontoparietal control system revealed by intrinsic functional connectivity. J. Neurophysiol. 100 , 3328–3342 (2008).

Niendam, T. A. et al. Meta-analytic evidence for a superordinate cognitive control network subserving diverse executive functions. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 12 , 241–268 (2012).

Spreng, R. N., Stevens, W. D., Chamberlain, J. P., Gilmore, A. W. & Schacter, D. L. Default network activity, coupled with the frontoparietal control network, supports goal-directed cognition. Neuroimage 53 , 303–317 (2010). This paper demonstrates how the DN couples with the FPCN for personally salient, goal-directed information processing.

Dixon, M. L., Fox, K. C. R. & Christoff, K. A framework for understanding the relationship between externally and internally directed cognition. Neuropsychologia 62 , 321–330 (2014).

Dosenbach, N. U. F. et al. A core system for the implementation of task sets. Neuron 50 , 799–812 (2006).

Dosenbach, N. U. F. et al. Distinct brain networks for adaptive and stable task control in humans. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 104 , 11073–11078 (2007).

Dosenbach, N. U. F., Fair, D. A., Cohen, A. L., Schlaggar, B. L. & Petersen, S. E. A dual-networks architecture of top-down control. Trends Cogn. Sci. 12 , 99–105 (2008).

Yeo, B. T. T. et al. The organization of the human cerebral cortex estimated by intrinsic functional connectivity. J. Neurophysiol. 106 , 1125–1165 (2011). This seminal paper uses resting-state functional connectivity and clustering approaches in 1,000 individuals to parcellate the brain into seven canonical large-scale networks.

Najafi, M., McMenamin, B. W., Simon, J. Z. & Pessoa, L. Overlapping communities reveal rich structure in large-scale brain networks during rest and task conditions. Neuroimage 135 , 92–106 (2016).

McGuire, P. K., Paulesu, E., Frackowiak, R. S. & Frith, C. D. Brain activity during stimulus independent thought. Neuroreport 7 , 2095–2099 (1996).

McKiernan, K. A., D'Angelo, B. R., Kaufman, J. N. & Binder, J. R. Interrupting the 'stream of consciousness': an fMRI investigation. Neuroimage 29 , 1185–1191 (2006).

Gilbert, S. J., Dumontheil, I., Simons, J. S., Frith, C. D. & Burgess, P. W. Comment on 'wandering minds: the default network and stimulus-independent thought'. Science 317 , 43b (2007).

Stawarczyk, D., Majerus, S., Maquet, P. & D'Argembeau, A. Neural correlates of ongoing conscious experience: both task-unrelatedness and stimulus-independence are related to default network activity. PLoS ONE 6 , e16997 (2011).

Fox, K. C. R., Spreng, R. N., Ellamil, M., Andrews-Hanna, J. R. & Christoff, K. The wandering brain: meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging studies of mind-wandering and related spontaneous thought processes. Neuroimage 111 , 611–621 (2015). This paper presents the first quantitative meta-analysis of neuroimaging studies on task-unrelated and/or stimulus-independent thought, revealing the involvement of the DN and other large-scale networks that were not traditionally thought to play a part in mind-wandering.

Ingvar, D. H. 'Hyperfrontal' distribution of the cerebral grey matter flow in resting wakefulness; on the functional anatomy of the conscious state. Acta Neurol. Scand. 60 , 12–25 (1979). This paper by David Ingvar, a pioneer of human neuroimaging, provides the original observations that a resting brain is an active one and highlights the finding that prefrontal executive regions are active even at rest.

Christoff, K., Ream, J. M. & Gabrieli, J. D. E. Neural basis of spontaneous thought processes. Cortex 40 , 623–630 (2004).

D'Argembeau, A. et al. Self-referential reflective activity and its relationship with rest: a PET study. Neuroimage 25 , 616–624 (2005).

Spiers, H. J. & Maguire, E. A. Spontaneous mentalizing during an interactive real world task: an fMRI study. Neuropsychologia 44 , 1674–1682 (2006).

Wang, K. et al. Offline memory reprocessing: involvement of the brain's default network in spontaneous thought processes. PLoS ONE 4 , e4867 (2009).

Dumontheil, I., Gilbert, S. J., Frith, C. D. & Burgess, P. W. Recruitment of lateral rostral prefrontal cortex in spontaneous and task-related thoughts. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 63 , 1740–1756 (2010).

Posner, M. I. & Rothbart, M. K. Attention, self-regulation and consciousness. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 353 , 1915–1927 (1998).

Duncan, J. & Owen, A. M. Common regions of the human frontal lobe recruited by diverse cognitive demands. Trends Neurosci. 23 , 475–483 (2000).

Botvinick, M. M., Braver, T. S., Barch, D. M., Carter, C. S. & Cohen, J. D. Conflict monitoring and cognitive control. Psychol. Rev. 108 , 624–652 (2001).

Banich, M. T. Executive function: the search for an integrated account. Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 18 , 89–94 (2009).

Prado, J., Chadha, A. & Booth, J. R. The brain network for deductive reasoning: a quantitative meta-analysis of 28 neuroimaging studies. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 23 , 3483–3497 (2011).

McVay, J. C. & Kane, M. J. Does mind wandering reflect executive function or executive failure? Comment on Smallwood and Schooler (2006) and Watkins (2008). Psychol. Bull. 136 , 188–197 (2010). This paper presents the theoretically influential control failure hypothesis, which is opposed to the thesis that executive function supports mind-wandering.

Kane, M. J. & McVay, J. C. What mind wandering reveals about executive-control abilities and failures. Curr. Direct. Psychol. Sci. 21 , 348–354 (2012).

Levinson, D. B., Smallwood, J. & Davidson, R. J. The persistence of thought: evidence for a role of working memory in the maintenance of task-unrelated thinking. Psychol. Sci. 23 , 375–380 (2012).

Salthouse, T. A., Fristoe, N., McGuthry, K. E. & Hambrick, D. Z. Relation of task switching to speed, age, and fluid intelligence. Psychol. Aging 13 , 445–461 (1998).

Maillet, D. & Schacter, D. L. From mind wandering to involuntary retrieval: age-related differences in spontaneous cognitive processes. Neuropsychologia 80 , 142–156 (2016).

Axelrod, V., Rees, G., Lavidor, M. & Bar, M. Increasing propensity to mind-wander with transcranial direct current stimulation. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 112 , 3314–3319 (2015).

Schooler, J. W. et al. Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends Cogn. Sci. 15 , 319–326 (2011).

Smallwood, J., Beach, E. & Schooler, J. W. Going AWOL in the brain: mind wandering reduces cortical analysis of external events. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 20 , 458–469 (2008).

Kam, J. W. Y. et al. Slow fluctuations in attentional control of sensory cortex. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 23 , 460–470 (2011).

Gelbard-Sagiv, H., Mukamel, R., Harel, M., Malach, R. & Fried, I. Internally generated reactivation of single neurons in human hippocampus during free recall. Science 322 , 96–101 (2008). This pioneering study aimed to identify the neural origins of spontaneously recalled memories, finding strong evidence for the initial generation in the MTL.

Ellamil, M. et al. Dynamics of neural recruitment surrounding the spontaneous arising of thoughts in experienced mindfulness practitioners. Neuroimage 136 , 186–196 (2016). This study is the first to reveal a sequential recruitment of the DN MTL , DN CORE , and FPCN immediately before, during and subsequent to the onset of spontaneous thoughts.

Andrews-Hanna, J. R., Reidler, J. S., Huang, C. & Buckner, R. L. Evidence for the default network's role in spontaneous cognition. J. Neurophysiol. 104 , 322–335 (2010).

Kucyi, A. & Davis, K. D. Dynamic functional connectivity of the default mode network tracks daydreaming. Neuroimage 100 , 471–480 (2014).

Foster, D. J. & Wilson, M. A. Reverse replay of behavioural sequences in hippocampal place cells during the awake state. Nature 440 , 680–683 (2006).

Karlsson, M. P. & Frank, L. M. Awake replay of remote experiences in the hippocampus. Nat. Neurosci. 12 , 913–918 (2009).

Carr, M. F., Jadhav, S. P. & Frank, L. M. Hippocampal replay in the awake state: a potential substrate for memory consolidation and retrieval. Nat. Neurosci. 14 , 147–153 (2011).

Dragoi, G. & Tonegawa, S. Distinct preplay of multiple novel spatial experiences in the rat. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 110 , 9100–9105 (2013).

Dragoi, G. & Tonegawa, S. Preplay of future place cell sequences by hippocampal cellular assemblies. Nature 469 , 397–401 (2011).

Ólafsdóttir, H. F., Barry, C., Saleem, A. B. & Hassabis, D. Hippocampal place cells construct reward related sequences through unexplored space. eLife 4 , e06063 (2015).

Stark, C. E. L. & Clark, R. E. The medial temporal lobe. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 27 , 279–306 (2004).

Moscovitch, M., Cabeza, R., Winocur, G. & Nadel, L. Episodic memory and beyond: the hippocampus and neocortex in transformation. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 67 , 105–134 (2016).

Romero, K. & Moscovitch, M. Episodic memory and event construction in aging and amnesia. J. Mem. Lang. 67 , 270–284 (2012).

Hassabis, D., Kumaran, D. & Maguire, E. A. Using imagination to understand the neural basis of episodic memory. J. Neurosci. 27 , 14365–14374 (2007).

Buckner, R. L. The role of the hippocampus in prediction and imagination. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 61 , 27–48 (2010).

Hassabis, D. & Maguire, E. A. The construction system of the brain. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 364 , 1263–1271 (2009).

Schacter, D. L. et al. The future of memory: remembering, imagining, and the brain. Neuron 76 , 677–694 (2012).

Schacter, D. L., Addis, D. R. & Buckner, R. L. Episodic simulation of future events: concepts, data, and applications. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 1124 , 39–60 (2008).

Moscovitch, M. Memory and working-with-memory: a component process model based on modules and central systems. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 4 , 257–267 (1992). This paper introduces the influential component process model of memory.

Teyler, T. J. & DiScenna, P. The hippocampal memory indexing theory. Behav. Neurosci. 100 , 147–154 (1986).

Moscovitch, M. The hippocampus as a “stupid,” domain-specific module: implications for theories of recent and remote memory, and of imagination. Can. J. Exp. Psychol. 62 , 62–79 (2008).

Bar, M., Aminoff, E., Mason, M. & Fenske, M. The units of thought. Hippocampus 17 , 420–428 (2007). This paper introduces a novel hypothesis on the associative processes underlying a train of thoughts, originating in the MTL.

Aminoff, E. M., Kveraga, K. & Bar, M. The role of the parahippocampal cortex in cognition. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17 , 379–390 (2013).

Christoff, K., Keramatian, K., Gordon, A. M., Smith, R. & Mädler, B. Prefrontal organization of cognitive control according to levels of abstraction. Brain Res. 1286 , 94–105 (2009).

Dixon, M. L., Fox, K. C. R. & Christoff, K. Evidence for rostro-caudal functional organization in multiple brain areas related to goal-directed behavior. Brain Res. 1572 , 26–39 (2014).

McCaig, R. G., Dixon, M., Keramatian, K., Liu, I. & Christoff, K. Improved modulation of rostrolateral prefrontal cortex using real-time fMRI training and meta-cognitive awareness. Neuroimage 55 , 1298–1305 (2011).

Dixon, M. L. & Christoff, K. The decision to engage cognitive control is driven by expected reward-value: neural and behavioral evidence. PLoS ONE 7 , e51637 (2012).

Yin, H. H. & Knowlton, B. J. The role of the basal ganglia in habit formation. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 7 , 464–476 (2006).

Burguière. E., Monteiro, P., Mallet, L., Feng, G. & Graybiel, A. M. Striatal circuits, habits, and implications for obsessive–compulsive disorder. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 30 , 59–65 (2015).

Mathews, A. & MacLeod, C. Cognitive vulnerability to emotional disorders. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 1 , 167–195 (2005).

Gotlib, I. H. & Joormann, J. Cognition and depression: current status and future directions. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 6 , 285–312 (2010).

Nolen-Hoeksema, S., Wisco, B. E. & Lyubomirsky, S. Rethinking rumination. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 3 , 400–424 (2008).

Watkins, E. R. Constructive and unconstructive repetitive thought. Psychol. Bull. 134 , 163–206 (2008). This comprehensive review and theory article links the psychological literature on task-unrelated or stimulus-independent thought to the clinical literature on rumination and other forms of repetitive thought, proposing multiple factors that govern whether repetitive thought is constructive or unconstructive.

Giambra, L. M. & Traynor, T. D. Depression and daydreaming; an analysis based on self-ratings. J. Clin. Psychol. 34 , 14–25 (1978).

Larsen, R. J. & Cowan, G. S. Internal focus of attention and depression: a study of daily experience. Motiv. Emot. 12 , 237–249 (1988).

Whitfield-Gabrieli, S. & Ford, J. M. Default mode network activity and connectivity in psychopathology. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol. 8 , 49–76 (2012).

Anticevic, A. et al. The role of default network deactivation in cognition and disease. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16 , 584–592 (2012).

Hamilton, J. P. et al. Functional neuroimaging of major depressive disorder: a meta-analysis and new integration of baseline activation and neural response data. Am. J. Psychiatry 169 , 693–703 (2012).

Kaiser, R. H. et al. Distracted and down: neural mechanisms of affective interference in subclinical depression. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 10 , 654–663 (2015).

Kaiser, R. H., Andrews-Hanna, J. R., Wager, T. D. & Pizzagalli, D. A. Large-scale network dysfunction in major depressive disorder. JAMA Psychiatry 72 , 603–637 (2015). This meta-analysis of resting-state functional connectivity studies in major depressive disorder provides quantitative support for functional-network imbalances, which reflect heightened internally focused thought in this disorder.

Kaiser, R. H. et al. Dynamic resting-state functional connectivity in major depression. Neuropsychopharmacology 41 , 1822–1830 (2015).

Spinhoven, P., Drost, J., van Hemert, B. & Penninx, B. W. Common rather than unique aspects of repetitive negative thinking are related to depressive and anxiety disorders and symptoms. J. Anxiety Disord. 33 , 45–52 (2015).

Borkovec, T. D., Ray, W. J. & Stober, J. Worry: a cognitive phenomenon intimately linked to affective, physiological, and interpersonal behavioral processes. Cognit. Ther. Res. 22 , 561–576 (1998).

Oathes, D. J., Patenaude, B., Schatzberg, A. F. & Etkin, A. Neurobiological signatures of anxiety and depression in resting-state functional magnetic resonance imaging. Biol. Psychiatry 77 , 385–393 (2015).

Bar-Haim, Y., Lamy, D., Pergamin, L., Bakermans-Kranenburg, M. J. & van IJzendoorn, M. H. Threat-related attentional bias in anxious and nonanxious individuals: a meta-analytic study. Psychol. Bull. 133 , 1–24 (2007).

Williams, J., Watts, F. N., MacLeod, C. & Mathews, A. Cognitive Psychology and Emotional Disorders (John Wiley & Sons, 1997).

Etkin, A., Prater, K. E., Schatzberg, A. F., Menon, V. & Greicius, M. D. Disrupted amygdalar subregion functional connectivity and evidence of a compensatory network in generalized anxiety disorder. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 66 , 1361–1372 (2009).

Ipser, J. C., Singh, L. & Stein, D. J. Meta-analysis of functional brain imaging in specific phobia. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci. 67 , 311–322 (2013).

American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (American Psychiatric Association, 2013).

Boonstra, A. M., Oosterlaan, J., Sergeant, J. A. & Buitelaar, J. K. Executive functioning in adult ADHD: a meta-analytic review. Psychol. Med. 35 , 1097–1108 (2005).

Willcutt, E. G., Doyle, A. E., Nigg, J. T., Faraone, S. V. & Pennington, B. F. Validity of the executive function theory of attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder: a meta-analytic review. Biol. Psychiatry 57 , 1336–1346 (2005).

Kofler, M. J. et al. Reaction time variability in ADHD: a meta-analytic review of 319 studies. Clin. Psychol. Rev. 33 , 795–811 (2013).

Shaw, G. A. & Giambra, L. Task unrelated thoughts of college students diagnosed as hyperactive in childhood. Dev. Neuropsychol. 9 , 17–30 (1993).

Franklin, M. S. et al. Tracking distraction: the relationship between mind-wandering, meta-awareness, and ADHD symptomatology. J. Atten. Disord. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1087054714543494 (2014).

De La Fuente, A., Xia, S., Branch, C. & Li, X. A review of attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder from the perspective of brain networks. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7 , 192 (2013).

Castellanos, F. X. & Proal, E. Large-scale brain systems in ADHD: beyond the prefrontal–striatal model. Trends Cogn. Sci. 16 , 17–26 (2012).

Hart, H., Radua, J., Mataix-Cols, D. & Rubia, K. Meta-analysis of fMRI studies of timing in attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 36 , 2248–2256 (2012).

Hart, H., Radua, J., Nakao, T., Mataix-Cols, D. & Rubia, K. Meta-analysis of functional magnetic resonance imaging studies of inhibition and attention in attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. JAMA Psychiatry 70 , 185–198 (2013).

Fassbender, C. et al. A lack of default network suppression is linked to increased distractibility in ADHD. Brain Res. 1273 , 114–128 (2009).

Cortese, S. et al. Toward systems neuroscience of ADHD: a meta-analysis of 55 fMRI studies. Am. J. Psychiatry 169 , 1038–1055 (2012).

Castellanos, F. X. et al. Cingulate-precuneus interactions: a new locus of dysfunction in adult attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. Biol. Psychiatry 63 , 332–337 (2008).

Uddin, L. Q. et al. Network homogeneity reveals decreased integrity of default-mode network in ADHD. J. Neurosci. Methods 169 , 249–254 (2008).

Tomasi, D. & Volkow, N. D. Abnormal functional connectivity in children with attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. Biol. Psychiatry 71 , 443–450 (2012).

Mattfeld, A. T. et al. Brain differences between persistent and remitted attention deficit hyperactivity disorder. Brain 137 , 2423–2428 (2014).

Sun, L. et al. Abnormal functional connectivity between the anterior cingulate and the default mode network in drug-naïve boys with attention deficit hyperactivity disorder. Psychiatry Res. 201 , 120–127 (2012).

McCarthy, H. et al. Attention network hypoconnectivity with default and affective network hyperconnectivity in adults diagnosed with attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder in childhood. JAMA Psychiatry 70 , 1329–1337 (2013).

Fair, D. A. et al. The maturing architecture of the brain's default network. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 105 , 4028–4032 (2008).

Sripada, C. et al. Disrupted network architecture of the resting brain in attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. Hum. Brain Mapp. 35 , 4693–4705 (2014). By analysing data from more than 750 participants, this paper links childhood ADHD to abnormal resting-state functional connectivity involving the DN.

Fair, D. A. et al. Atypical default network connectivity in youth with attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder. Biol. Psychiatry 68 , 1084–1091 (2010).

Anderson, A. et al. Non-negative matrix factorization of multimodal MRI, fMRI and phenotypic data reveals differential changes in default mode subnetworks in ADHD. Neuroimage 102 , 207–219 (2014).

Power, J. D., Barnes, K. A., Snyder, A. Z., Schlaggar, B. L. & Petersen, S. E. Spurious but systematic correlations in functional connectivity MRI networks arise from subject motion. Neuroimage 59 , 2142–2154 (2012).

Van Dijk, K. R. A., Sabuncu, M. R. & Buckner, R. L. The influence of head motion on intrinsic functional connectivity MRI. Neuroimage 59 , 431–438 (2012).

Sonuga-Barke, E. J. S. & Castellanos, F. X. Spontaneous attentional fluctuations in impaired states and pathological conditions: a neurobiological hypothesis. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev. 31 , 977–986 (2007).

Kerns, J. G. & Berenbaum, H. Cognitive impairments associated with formal thought disorder in people with schizophrenia. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 111 , 211–224 (2002).

Videbeck, S. L. Psychiatric Mental Health Nursing (Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2006).

Hales, R. E., Yudofsky, S. C. & Roberts, L. W. The American Psychiatric Publishing Textbook of Psychiatry 6th edn (American Psychiatric Publishing, 2014).

Haijma, S. V. et al. Brain volumes in schizophrenia: a meta-analysis in over 18 000 subjects. Schizophr. Bull. 39 , 1129–1138 (2013).

Glahn, D. C. et al. Meta-analysis of gray matter anomalies in schizophrenia: application of anatomic likelihood estimation and network analysis. Biol. Psychiatry 64 , 774–781 (2008).

Fornito, A., Yücel, M., Patti, J., Wood, S. J. & Pantelis, C. Mapping grey matter reductions in schizophrenia: an anatomical likelihood estimation analysis of voxel-based morphometry studies. Schizophr. Res. 108 , 104–113 (2009).

Ellison-Wright, I. & Bullmore, E. Anatomy of bipolar disorder and schizophrenia: a meta-analysis. Schizophr. Res. 117 , 1–12 (2010).

Vita, A., De Peri, L., Deste, G., Barlati, S. & Sacchetti, E. The effect of antipsychotic treatment on cortical gray matter changes in schizophrenia: does the class matter? A meta-analysis and meta-regression of longitudinal magnetic resonance imaging studies. Biol. Psychiatry 78 , 403–412 (2015).

Cole, M. W., Anticevic, A., Repovs, G. & Barch, D. Variable global dysconnectivity and individual differences in schizophrenia. Biol. Psychiatry 70 , 43–50 (2011).

Argyelan, M. et al. Resting-state fMRI connectivity impairment in schizophrenia and bipolar disorder. Schizophr. Bull. 40 , 100–110 (2014).

Cole, M. W., Yarkoni, T., Repovs, G., Anticevic, A. & Braver, T. S. Global connectivity of prefrontal cortex predicts cognitive control and intelligence. J. Neurosci. 32 , 8988–8999 (2012).

Baker, J. T. et al. Disruption of cortical association networks in schizophrenia and psychotic bipolar disorder. JAMA Psychiatry 71 , 109–110 (2014).

Karbasforoushan, H. & Woodward, N. D. Resting-state networks in schizophrenia. Curr. Top. Med. Chem. 12 , 2404–2414 (2013).

Jafri, M. J., Pearlson, G. D., Stevens, M. & Calhoun, V. D. A method for functional network connectivity among spatially independent resting-state components in schizophrenia. Neuroimage 39 , 1666–1681 (2008).

Whitfield-Gabrieli, S. et al. Hyperactivity and hyperconnectivity of the default network in schizophrenia and in first-degree relatives of persons with schizophrenia. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 106 , 1279–1284 (2009).

Palaniyappan, L., Simmonite, M., White, T. P., Liddle, E. B. & Liddle, P. F. Neural primacy of the salience processing system in schizophrenia. Neuron 79 , 814–828 (2013).

Mittner, M., Hawkins, G. E., Boekel, W. & Forstmann, B. U. A neural model of mind wandering. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20 , 570–578 (2016). This paper convincingly argues for the introduction of two important novel elements to the scientific study of mind-wandering: employing cognitive modelling and a consideration of neuromodulatory influences on thought.

Fox, K. C. R. & Christoff, K. in The Cognitive Neuroscience of Metacognition (eds Fleming, S. M. & Frith, C. D.) 293–319 (Springer, 2014).

Foulkes, D. & Fleisher, S. Mental activity in relaxed wakefulness. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 84 , 66–75 (1975).

Fox, K. C. R., Nijeboer, S., Solomonova, E., Domhoff, G. W. & Christoff, K. Dreaming as mind wandering: evidence from functional neuroimaging and first-person content reports. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7 , 412 (2013).

De Bono, E. Six Thinking Hats (Little Brown and Company, 1985).

Ellamil, M., Dobson, C., Beeman, M. & Christoff, K. Evaluative and generative modes of thought during the creative process. Neuroimage 59 , 1783–1794 (2012).

Beaty, R. E., Benedek, M., Kaufman, S. B. & Silvia, P. J. Default and executive network coupling supports creative idea production. Sci. Rep. 5 , 10964 (2015).

Fox, K. C. R., Kang, Y., Lifshitz, M. & Christoff, K. in Hypnosis and Meditation (eds Raz, A. & Lifshitz, M.) 191–210 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2016).

Fazelpour, S. & Thompson, E. The Kantian brain: brain dynamics from a neurophenomenological perspective. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 31 , 223–229 (2015).

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors are grateful to R. Buckner, P. Carruthers, M. Cuddy-Keane, M. Dixon, S. Fazelpour, D. Stan, E. Thompson, R. Todd and the anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful feedback on earlier versions of this paper, and to A. Herrera-Bennett for help with the figure preparation. K.C. was supported by grants from the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council (NSERC) (RGPIN 327317–11) and the Canadian Institutes of Health Research (CIHR) (MOP-115197). Z.C.I. was supported by a Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada (SSHRC) postdoctoral fellowship, the Balzan Styles of Reasoning Project and a Templeton Integrated Philosophy and Self Control grant. K.C.R.F. was supported by a Vanier Canada Graduate Scholarship. R.N.S. was supported by an Alzheimer's Association grant (NIRG-14-320049). J.R.A.-H. was supported by a Templeton Science of Prospection grant.

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, 2136 West Mall, Vancouver, V6T 1Z4, British Columbia, Canada

Kalina Christoff & Kieran C. R. Fox

Centre for Brain Health, University of British Columbia, 2211 Wesbrook Mall, Vancouver, V6T 2B5, British Columbia, Canada

Kalina Christoff

Departments of Philosophy and Psychology, University of California, Berkeley, 94720, California, USA

Zachary C. Irving

Department of Human Development, Laboratory of Brain and Cognition, Cornell University,

R. Nathan Spreng

Human Neuroscience Institute, Cornell University, Ithaca, 14853, New York, USA

Institute of Cognitive Science, University of Colorado Boulder, UCB 594, Boulder, 80309–0594, Colorado, USA

Jessica R. Andrews-Hanna

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kalina Christoff .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The authors declare no competing financial interests.

PowerPoint slides

Powerpoint slide for fig. 1, powerpoint slide for fig. 2, powerpoint slide for fig. 3, powerpoint slide for fig. 4, powerpoint slide for fig. 5.

A mental state, or a sequence of mental states, including the transitions that lead to each state.

A transient cognitive or emotional state of the organism that can be described in terms of its contents (what the state is 'about') and the relation that the subject bears to the contents (for example, perceiving, believing, fearing, imagining or remembering).

Thoughts with contents that are unrelated to what the person having those thoughts is currently doing.

Thinking that is characteristically fanciful (that is, divorced from physical or social reality); it can either be spontaneous, as in fanciful mind-wandering, or constrained, as during deliberately fantasizing about a topic.

A thought with contents that are unrelated to the current external perceptual environment.

A deliberate guidance of current thoughts, perceptions or actions, which is imposed in a goal-directed manner by currently active top-down executive processes.

The emotional significance of percepts, thoughts or other elements of mental experience, which can draw and sustain attention through mechanisms outside of cognitive control.

Features of current perceptual experience, such as high perceptual contrast, which can draw and sustain attention through mechanisms outside of cognitive control.

The process of spontaneously or deliberately inferring one's own or other agents' mental states.

Flexible combinations of distinct elements of prior experiences, constructed in the process of imagining a novel (often future-oriented) event.

A type of dreaming during which the dreamer is aware that he or she is currently dreaming and, in some cases, can have deliberate control over dream content and progression.

The ability to produce ideas that are both novel (that is, original and unique) and useful (that is, appropriate and meaningful).

A method in which participants are probed at random intervals and asked to report on aspects of their subjective experience immediately before the probe.

Different ways of categorizing a thought based on its contents, including stimulus dependence (whether the thought is about stimuli that one is currently perceiving), task relatedness (whether the thought is about the current task), modality (visual, auditory, and so on), valence (whether the thought is negative, neutral or positive) or temporal orientation (whether the thought is about the past, present or future).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Christoff, K., Irving, Z., Fox, K. et al. Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework. Nat Rev Neurosci 17 , 718–731 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.113

Download citation

Published : 22 September 2016

Issue Date : November 2016

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.113

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

This article is cited by

Evidence synthesis indicates contentless experiences in meditation are neither truly contentless nor identical.

  • Toby J. Woods
  • Jennifer M. Windt
  • Olivia Carter

Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences (2024)

The mediating role of default mode network during meaning-making aroused by mental simulation between stressful events and stress-related growth: a task fMRI study

Behavioral and Brain Functions (2023)

The role of memory in creative ideation

  • Mathias Benedek
  • Roger E. Beaty
  • Yoed N. Kenett

Nature Reviews Psychology (2023)

A tripartite view of the posterior cingulate cortex

  • Brett L. Foster
  • Seth R. Koslov
  • Sarah R. Heilbronner

Nature Reviews Neuroscience (2023)

Effect of subconscious changes in bodily response on thought shifting in people with accurate interoception

  • Mai Sakuragi
  • Kazushi Shinagawa
  • Satoshi Umeda

Scientific Reports (2023)

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

mind wandering significato

Frontiers for Young Minds

Frontiers for Young Minds

  • Download PDF

The Wandering Mind: How the Brain Allows Us to Mentally Wander Off to Another Time and Place

mind wandering significato

A unique human characteristic is our ability to mind wander—these are periods of time when our attention drifts away from the task-at-hand to focus on thoughts that are unrelated to the task. Mind wandering has some benefits, such as increased creativity, but it also has some negative consequences, such as mistakes in the task we are supposed to be performing. Interestingly, we spend up to half of our waking hours mind wandering. How does the brain help us accomplish that? Research suggests that when we mind wander, our responses to information from the external world around us are disrupted. In other words, our brain’s resources are shifted away from processing information from the external environment and redirected to our internal world, which allows us to mentally wander off to another time and place. Even though we pay less attention to the external world during mind wandering, our ability to detect unexpected events in our surrounding environment is preserved. This suggests that we are quite clever about what we ignore or pay attention to in the external environment, even when we mind wander.

How Do Scientists Define Mind Wandering?

Imagine this: you are sitting in a classroom on a sunny day as your science teacher enthusiastically tells you what our brain is capable of doing. Initially, you pay close attention to what the teacher is saying. But the sound of the words coming out of her mouth gradually fade away as you notice your stomach growling and you begin to think about that delicious ice cream you had last night. Have you ever caught yourself mind wandering in similar situations, where your eyes are fixed on your teacher, friends, or parents, but your mind has secretly wandered off to another time and place? You may be recalling the last sports game you watched, or fantasizing about going to the new amusement park this upcoming weekend, or humming your favorite tune that you just cannot get out of your head. This experience is what scientists call mind wandering, which is a period of time when we are focused on things that are not related to the ongoing task or what is actually going on around us (as shown in Figure 1 ).

Figure 1 - Real-world example of on-task and mind wandering states among students in a classroom.

  • Figure 1 - Real-world example of on-task and mind wandering states among students in a classroom.
  • In a science class in which the teacher asks a question about the brain, some students may be focused on what is being taught, while others may be thinking about yesterday’s basketball tournament, humming their favorite tune, or thinking about getting ice cream after school. The students thinking about the brain during class would be considered to be “on task,” while students thinking about things unrelated to the brain would be considered to be “mind wandering.”

Our Tendency to Mind Wander

Humans on average spend up to half of their waking hours mind wandering. There are differences across individuals in their tendency to mind wander and many factors that affect this tendency. For instance, older adults on average tend to mind wander less than younger adults. Also, individuals who are often sad or worried mind wander more frequently compared with individuals who are happy and have nothing to worry about. We also mind wander more when we perform tasks that we are used to doing, compared with when we perform novel and challenging tasks. There are also different types of mind wandering. For example, we may sometimes mind wander on purpose when we are bored with what we are currently doing. Other times, our mind accidentally wanders off without us noticing.

What are the Pros and Cons of Mind Wandering?

Since we spend so much time mind wandering, does this mean that mind wandering is good for us or not? There are certainly benefits to mind wandering. For example, one of the things the mind does when it wanders is to make plans about the future. In fact, we are more likely to make plans when we mind wander than we are to fantasize about unrealistic situations. Planning ahead is a good use of time as it allows us to efficiently carry out our day-to-day tasks, such as finishing homework, practicing soccer, and preparing for a performance. When mind wandering, we are also likely to reflect upon ourselves. This process of thinking about how we think, behave, and interact with others around us is a crucial part of our self-identity. Mind wandering has also been tied to creative problem-solving. There are times when we get stuck on a challenging math problem or feel uninspired to paint or make music, and research suggests that taking a break from thinking about these problems and letting the mind wander off to another topic may eventually lead to an “aha” moment, in which we come up with a creative solution or idea.

However, mind wandering can also have negative outcomes. For example, mind wandering in class means you miss out on what is being taught, and mind wandering while doing your homework may result in mistakes. Taken to an extreme, people who are diagnosed with depression constantly engage in their own thoughts about their problems or other negative experiences. In contrast, individuals diagnosed with attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder who continually change their focus of attention may have a hard time completing a task. Taken together, whether mind wandering is good or bad depends on when we mind wander and what we mind wander about [ 1 ].

Scientific Measures of Mind Wandering

If you were to conduct an experiment, how would you measure mind wandering? Scientists have come up with several methods, one of which is called experience sampling . As research volunteers are doing a computer task in a laboratory, or as they are doing chores in their day-to-day lives, they are asked at random intervals to report their attention state. That is, they have to stop what they are doing and ask themselves what they were thinking about in the moment: “Was I on-task?” (that is, was I paying attention to the task-at-hand) or “Was I mind wandering?” (that is, did my mind wander off to another time and place). Therefore, experience sampling samples the volunteer’s in-the-moment experience, allowing scientists to understand how frequently people mind wander and how mind wandering affects the way people interact with their environments.

Scientists also study mind wandering by recording electroencephalogram (EEG) , a test that measures the electrical activity of the brain. This electrical activity, which looks like wavy lines during an EEG recording (see Figure 2 , Step 2), is observed in all parts of the brain and is present throughout the day, even when we are asleep. Measurements of the brain’s electrical activity help scientists understand how the brain allows us to think, speak, move, and do all the fun and creative and challenging things that we do! In order to record EEG, scientists place special sensors called electrodes on the scalp of a volunteer ( Figure 2 , Step 1), with each electrode recording activity of numerous neurons (brain cells) in the area under the electrode ( Figure 2 , Step 2). Scientists then examine the brain’s activity in response to images (such as a picture of a basketball in Figure 2 ) or sounds presented to the volunteer. The scientists present the same sound or picture to the volunteer multiple times and take the average of the brain’s activity in response to the image or sound, because that method results in a better EEG signal. The averaged brain activity produces something called an event-related potential (ERP) waveform that contains several high and low points, called peaks and troughs ( Figure 2 , Step 3), which represent the brain’s response to the image or sound over time. Some commonly seen peaks and troughs are assigned specific names as ERP components. For instance, a peak that occurs around 300 ms (only 3/10 of a second!) following the presentation of a picture or a sound is often called the P300 ERP component. Based on decades of research, scientists have shown that these ERP components reflect our brain’s response to events we see or hear. The size of the ERP components (measured in voltage) reflects how strong the response is, while the timing of these ERP components (measured in milliseconds) reflects the timing of the response. Now, PAUSE! I would like you to ask yourself, “Was I paying full attention to the previous sentence just now, or was I thinking about something else?” This is an example of experience sampling. And as you may realize now, when we are asked about our current attention state, we can quite accurately report it.

Figure 2 - Recording electroencephalogram (EEG) in humans.

  • Figure 2 - Recording electroencephalogram (EEG) in humans.
  • Step 1. To record EEG, electrodes are attached to a cap that is placed on the scalp of a research volunteer. Step 2. Each wavy line represents the amount of activity recorded by each electrode. Research volunteers are usually presented with some images (e.g., a basketball) or sounds a number of times while their brain activity is being recorded. Step 3. Scientists calculate the average EEG activity across multiple presentations of the same picture/sound. This results in an Event-Related Potential (ERP) waveform, where time (in milliseconds) is plotted on the x-axis and the voltage (in microvolts, indicating the size of the ERP components) is plotted on the y-axis. On the x-axis, 0 indicates the time at which the stimulus (e.g., image of a basketball) was presented. The ERP waveforms contain multiple high and low points, called peaks and troughs. Some of the peaks and troughs are given specific labels. For example, the peak that occurs around 300 ms after an image is presented is often called the P300 ERP component.

What Happens to Our Interaction with the Environment When We Mind Wander?

Scientists have proposed an idea—called the “Decoupling Hypothesis”—stating that during mind wandering, the brain’s resources are shifted away from our surrounding environment and are redirected to our internal world in order to support our thoughts [ 2 ]. This hypothesis assumes that the brain has a certain amount of resources, which means that once mind wandering has used the resources it needs to focus on our thoughts, only a limited amount of brain resources remains for responding to our surrounding environment.

To test this hypothesis, scientists combined experience sampling with EEG to explore how mind wandering affects our interaction with the environment. One of the first studies to test this hypothesis asked research volunteers to categorize a series of images by responding whenever they saw rare targets (e.g., images of soccer balls) among a whole bunch of non-targets (e.g., images of basketballs). Throughout the task, EEG was recorded from the volunteers, and they were also asked at random times to report their attention state as “on task” or “mind wandering.” Based on their EEGs and experience sampling reports, scientists found that the brain’s response to the non-targets was reduced during periods of mind wandering compared with periods of being on task [ 3 ]. This can be seen in Figure 3A , where there is a smaller P300 ERP component during mind wandering (the green lines) compared with the P300 ERP component during the time when the volunteer was on task (the gray line). The data suggest that the brain’s response to events happening in our environment is disrupted when we engage in mind wandering.

Figure 3 - Mind wandering affects our ability to process events in the environment.

  • Figure 3 - Mind wandering affects our ability to process events in the environment.
  • A. The brain’s processing of external events (e.g., images of basketballs and soccer balls) is reduced during periods of mind wandering. This is indicated by the smaller P300 ERP component during mind wandering (green lines) compared with on-task (gray line). The ERP waveform was recorded from the electrode site circled in red, which is located on the back of the head. B. Mind wandering impairs our ability to monitor our own performance, making it more likely that we will make mistakes. This is shown by the smaller feedback error-related negativity ERP component, a trough occurring around 250 ms, for mind wandering (green line) compared with on-task (gray line). The ERP waveform was recorded from the electrode site circled in red, which is located near the front of the head.

Have you ever noticed that if your mind wanders while you are doing homework, you are more likely to make mistakes? Many experiments have also shown that this happens! This led some scientists to question what is happening in the brain when we make mistakes. They specifically measured something called the feedback error-related negativity ERP component, which gives scientists an idea of how closely we are monitoring the accuracy of our responses when we perform a task. The scientists found that the feedback error-related negativity ERP component was reduced during mind wandering compared with on-task periods, as shown in Figure 3B . This suggests that mind wandering negatively affects our ability to monitor our performance and adjust our behavior, making it more likely that we will make mistakes [ 4 ]. All of these studies provide evidence supporting the hypothesis that when the mind wanders, our responses to what is going on in the environment around us are disrupted.

Does Mind Wandering Impair all Responses to the Environment?

At this point, you may wonder: are all responses to the world around us impaired during mind wandering? This seems unlikely, because we are usually quite capable of responding to the external environment even when we mind wander. For example, even though we may mind wander a lot while walking, most of us rarely bump into things as we walk from place to place. A group of scientists asked the same question and looked specifically at whether we can still pay attention to our environment at some level even when we are mind wandering. To test this question, research volunteers were asked to read a book while they were listening to some tones unrelated to the book. Most of the tones were identical, but among these identical tones was rare and different tone that naturally grabbed the attention of the volunteers. These scientists found that the volunteers paid just as much attention to this rare tone when they were mind wandering compared to when they were on task. In other words, our minds appear to be quite smart about which attention processes to disrupt and which processes to preserve during mind wandering. Under normal circumstances, our minds ignore some of the ordinary events in our environment in order for us to maintain a train of thought. However, when an unexpected event occurs in the environment, one that is potentially dangerous, our brain knows to shift our attention to the external environment so that we can respond to the potentially dangerous event. Imagine walking down the street and thinking about the movie you want to watch this weekend. While doing this, you may not clearly perceive the noise of the car engines or the pedestrians chatting around you. However, if a car suddenly honks loudly, you will hear the honk immediately, which will snap you out of your mind wandering. Therefore, even when the mind is wandering, we are still clever about what we ignore and what we pay attention to in the external environment, allowing us to smartly respond to the unusual, or potentially dangerous, events that may require us to focus our attention back on the external environment.

In summary, the brain appears to support mind wandering by disrupting some of the brain processes that are involved in responding to our surrounding external environment. This ability is important for protecting our thoughts from external distractions and allowing us to fully engage in mind wandering. We are only beginning to understand this mysterious experience of thinking, and scientists are actively researching what goes on in the brain when we mind wander. Increasing our knowledge about mind wandering will help us better understand how to take advantage of its benefits while avoiding the problems linked to mind wandering.

Mind Wandering : ↑ Periods of time when an individual is thinking of something that is unrelated to the task he/she is performing.

Experience Sampling : ↑ A scientific method in which a person is asked to report their experience; that is, whether he or she is paying attention or mind wandering at random intervals in the laboratory setting or in the real world.

Electroenceph-Alogram (EEG—“elec-tro-en-sef-a-lo-gram”) : ↑ Electrical activity of many neurons in the brain that is measured by electrodes placed on the scalp.

Event-Related Potential (ERPs) : ↑ Peaks or troughs in the averaged EEG signal that reflect the brain’s responses to events we see or hear.

P300 : ↑ An ERP component that typically peaks around 300 ms (therefore “300”) after a person sees a picture or hears a sound. It reflects the brain’s processing of the information that is seen or heard. an ERP component that typically peaks around 300 ms (therefore “300”) after a person sees a picture or hears a sound. It reflects the brain’s processing of the information that is seen or heard.

Feedback Error-Related Negativity : ↑ An ERP component that reflects how much a person is monitoring the accuracy of his/her performance.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

[1] ↑ Smallwood, J., and Andrews-Hanna, J. 2013. Not all minds that wander are lost: the importance of a balanced perspective on the mind-wandering state. Front. Psychol. 4:441. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00441

[2] ↑ Smallwood, J. 2013. Distinguishing how from why the mind wanders: a process-occurrence framework for self-generated mental activity. Psychol. Bull. 139(2013):519–35. doi:10.1037/a0030010

[3] ↑ Smallwood, J., Beach, E., Schooler, J. W., and Handy, T. C. 2008. Going AWOL in the brain: mind wandering cortical analysis of external events. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 20:458–69. doi:10.1162/jocn.2008.20037

[4] ↑ Kam, J. W. Y., Dao, E., Blinn, P., Krigolson, O. E., Boyd, L. A., and Handy, T. C. 2012. Mind wandering and motor control: off-task thinking disrupts the online adjustment of behavior. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6:329. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2012.00329

Nir Eyal

How to Tame Your Wandering Mind

Learn to take steps to deal with distraction..

Posted April 24, 2022 | Reviewed by Jessica Schrader

  • Understanding Attention
  • Find counselling to help with ADHD
  • We can tame our mind-wandering.
  • Three tips can help you use mind-wandering to your advantage.
  • These include making time to mind-wander and controlling your response to it.

Nir and Far

Researchers believe that when a task isn’t sufficiently rewarding, our brains search for something more interesting to think about.

You have a big deadline looming, and it’s time to hunker down. But every time you start working, you find that, for some reason, your mind drifts off before you can get any real work done. What gives? What is this cruel trick our brains play on us, and what do we do about it?

Thankfully, by understanding why our mind wanders and taking steps to deal with distraction, we can stay on track. But first, let’s understand the root of the problem.

Why do our minds wander?

Unintentional mind-wandering occurs when our thoughts are not tied to the task at hand. Researchers believe our minds wander when the thing we’re supposed to be doing is not sufficiently rewarding, so our brains look for something more interesting to think about.

We’ve all experienced it from time to time, but it’s important to note that some people struggle with chronic mind-wandering : Though studies estimate ADHD afflicts less than 3% of the global adult population, it can be a serious problem and may require medical intervention.

For the vast majority of people, mind-wandering is something we can tame on our own—that is, if we know what to do about it. In fact, according to Professor Ethan Kross, director of the Emotion & Self Control Laboratory at the University of Michigan and author of Chatter: The Voice in Our Head, Why It Matters, and How to Harness It , mind-wandering is perfectly normal.

“We spend between a third to a half of our waking hours not focused on the present,” he told me in an email. “Some neuroscience research refers to our tendency to mind-wander as our ‘default state.’”

So why do we do it?

“Mind-wandering serves several valuable functions. It helps us simulate and plan for the future and learn from our past, and it facilitates creative problem-solving,” Kross explained. “Mind-wandering often gets a bad rep, but it’s a psychological process that evolved to provide us with a competitive advantage. Imagine not being able to plan for the future or learn from your past mistakes.”

Is mind-wandering bad for you?

“Like any psychological tool, however, mind-wandering can be harmful if used in the wrong context (i.e., when you’re trying to focus on a task) or inappropriately (i.e., when you worry or ruminate too much),” according to Kross. In other words, mind-wandering is a problem when it becomes a distraction. A distraction is any action that pulls you away from what you planned to do.

If, for instance, you intended to work on a big project, such as writing a blog post or finishing a proposal, but instead find yourself doing something else, you’re distracted.

Nir And Far

The good news is that we can use mind-wandering to our advantage if we follow a few simple steps:

1. Make time to mind-wander

Mind-wandering isn’t always a distraction. If we plan for it, we can turn mind-wandering into traction. Unlike a distraction , which by definition is a bad thing, a diversion is simply a refocusing of attention and isn’t always harmful.

There’s nothing wrong with deciding to refocus your attention for a while. In fact, we often enjoy all kinds of diversions and pay for the privilege.

A movie or a good book, for instance, diverts our attention away from real life for a while so we can get into the story and escape reality for a bit.

Similarly, if you make time to allow your mind to drift and explore whatever it likes, that’s a healthy diversion, not a distraction.

The first step to mastering mind-wandering is to plan time for it. Use a schedule maker and block off time in your day to let your thoughts flow freely. You’ll likely find that a few minutes spent in contemplation can help you work through unresolved issues and lead to breakthroughs. Scheduling mind-wandering also lets you relax because you know you have time to think about whatever is on your mind instead of believing you need to act on every passing thought.

It’s helpful to know that time to think is on your calendar so you don’t have to interrupt your mind-wandering process or risk getting distracted later.

2. Catch the action

One of the difficulties surrounding mind-wandering is that by the time you notice you’re doing it, you’ve already done it. It’s an unconscious process so you can’t prevent it from happening.

mind wandering significato

The good news is that while you can’t stop your mind from wandering, you can control what you do when it happens.

Many people never learn that they are not their thoughts. They believe the voice in their head is somehow a special part of them, like their soul speaking out their inner desires and true self. When random thoughts cross their mind, they think those thoughts must be speaking some important truth.

Not true. That voice in your head is not your soul talking, nor do you have to believe everything you think.

When we assign undue importance to the chatter in our heads, we risk listening to half-baked ideas, feeling shame for intrusive thoughts, or acting impulsively against our best interests.

A much healthier way to view mind-wandering is as brain static. Just as the random radio frequencies you tune through don’t reveal the inner desires of your car’s soul, the thoughts you have while mind-wandering don’t mean much—unless, that is, you act upon them.

Though it can throw us off track, mind-wandering generally only lasts a few seconds, maybe minutes. However, when we let mind-wandering turn into other distractions, such as social-media scrolling, television-channel surfing, or news-headline checking, that’s when we risk wasting hours rather than mere minutes.

If you do find yourself mentally drifting off in the middle of a task, the important thing is to not allow that to become an unintended action, and therefore a distraction.

An intrusive thought is not your fault. It can’t be controlled. What matters is how you respond to it—hence the word respon-sibility.

Do you let the thought go and stay on task? Or do you allow yourself to escape what you’re doing by letting it lead you toward an action you’ll later regret?

3. Note and refocus

Can we keep the helpful aspects of mind-wandering while doing away with the bad? For the most part, yes, we can.

According to Kross, “Mind-wandering can easily shift into dysfunctional worry and rumination. When that happens, the options are to refocus on the present or to implement tools that help people mind-wander more effectively.”

One of the best ways to harness the power of mind-wandering while doing an important task is to quickly note the thought you don’t want to lose on a piece of paper. It’s a simple tactic anyone can use but few bother to do. Note that I didn’t recommend an app or sending yourself an email. Tech tools are full of external triggers that can tempt us to just check “one quick thing,” and before we know it, we’re distracted.

Rather, a pen and Post-it note or a notepad are the ideal tools to get ideas out of your head without the temptations that may lead you away from what you planned to do.

Then, you can collect your thoughts and check back on them later during the time you’ve planned in your day to chew on your ideas. If you give your thoughts a little time, you’ll often find that those super important ideas aren’t so important after all.

If you had acted on them at the moment, they would have wasted your time. But by writing them down and revisiting them when you’ve planned to do so, they have time to marinate and may become less relevant.

However, once in a while, an idea you collected will turn out to be a gem. With the time you planned to chew on the thought, you may discover that mind-wandering spurred you to a great insight you can explore later.

By following the three steps above, you’ll be able to master mind-wandering rather than letting it become your master.

Nir Eyal

Nir Eyal, who has lectured at Stanford's Graduate School of Business and the Hasso Plattner Institute of Design, is the author of Indistractable: How to Control Your Attention and Choose Your Life.

  • Find a Therapist
  • Find a Treatment Center
  • Find a Support Group
  • International
  • New Zealand
  • South Africa
  • Switzerland
  • Asperger's
  • Bipolar Disorder
  • Chronic Pain
  • Eating Disorders
  • Passive Aggression
  • Personality
  • Goal Setting
  • Positive Psychology
  • Stopping Smoking
  • Low Sexual Desire
  • Relationships
  • Child Development
  • Therapy Center NEW
  • Diagnosis Dictionary
  • Types of Therapy

March 2024 magazine cover

Understanding what emotional intelligence looks like and the steps needed to improve it could light a path to a more emotionally adept world.

  • Coronavirus Disease 2019
  • Affective Forecasting
  • Neuroscience
  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Acquisition
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Religion
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Society
  • Law and Politics
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business History
  • Business Strategy
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Theory
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

The Oxford Handbook of Spontaneous Thought: Mind-Wandering, Creativity, and Dreaming

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

The Oxford Handbook of Spontaneous Thought: Mind-Wandering, Creativity, and Dreaming

8 The Philosophy of Mind-Wandering

Zachary C. Irving Departments of Philosophy and Psychology University of California, Berkeley Berkeley, California, United States

Evan Thompson Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada

  • Published: 05 April 2018
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This chapter provides an introduction to the philosophy of mind-wandering. It begins with a philosophical critique of the standard psychological definitions of mind-wandering as task-unrelated thought or stimulus-independent thought. Although these definitions have helped bring mind-wandering research onto center stage in psychology and cognitive neuroscience, they have substantial limitations. They do not account for the dynamics of mind-wandering, task-unrelated thought that does not qualify as mind-wandering, or the ways in which mind-wandering can be task-related. The chapter reviews philosophical accounts that improve upon the current psychological definitions, in particular an account of mind-wandering as “unguided thinking.” It critically assesses the view that mind-wandering can be defined as thought lacking meta-awareness and cognitive agency, as well as the view that mind-wandering is disunified thinking. The definition of mind-wandering as unguided thinking not only is conceptually and phenomenologically precise, but also can be operationalized in a principled way for empirical research.

Before the twenty-first century, research on the wandering mind was “relegated to the backwaters of mainstream empirical psychology” ( Smallwood & Schooler, 2006 , p. 956). Not anymore. Indeed, some researchers have dubbed our time “the era of the wandering mind” ( Callard, Smallwood, Golchert, & Margulies, 2013 ). Nevertheless, because the cognitive science of mind-wandering is so young, foundational questions remain unanswered. In particular, there is no consensus about how to define mind-wandering ( Christoff, 2012 ; Irving, 2016 ), although recent philosophical work on mind-wandering has addressed this foundational issue ( Carruthers, 2015 ; Dorsch, 2015 ; Irving, 2016 ; Metzinger, 2013 , 2015 ; Sutton, 2010 ; Thompson, 2015 ). In this chapter, we provide an introduction to the philosophy of mind-wandering, and we argue that mind-wandering is best defined as “unguided thinking” ( Irving, 2016 ).

We begin by criticizing the standard definitions of mind-wandering in psychology, according to which mind-wandering is “task-unrelated thought” or “stimulus-independent thought” (see Irving, 2016 ). Scientists have used these definitions to produce important findings and bring mind-wandering into center stage in psychology and cognitive neuroscience ( Schooler, Smallwood, Christoff, Handy, Reichle, & Sayette, 2011 ; Smallwood & Schooler, 2006 , 2015 ). Nevertheless, these definitions have substantial limitations that must be overcome in order for research to move forward. Specifically, the standard definitions do not account for (1) the dynamics of mind wandering, (2) task-unrelated thought that does not qualify as mind-wandering, and (3) the ways that mind-wandering can be task-related.

We then survey three philosophical accounts that improve upon the current psychological definitions in various ways. We first present our account of mind-wandering as “unguided thinking” ( Irving, 2016 ). Next, we review Thomas Metzinger’s (2013) view that mind-wandering can be defined as thought lacking meta-awareness and cognitive agency, as well as Peter Carruthers’s (2015) and Fabian Dorsch’s (2015) definitions of mind-wandering as disunified thinking. We argue that these views are inadequate, and we show that our definition of mind-wandering as unguided thinking not only is conceptually and phenomenologically precise, but also can be operationalized in a principled way for empirical research.

Mind-Wandering as Task-Unrelated Thought or Stimulus-Independent Thought

Experientially, we all know mind-wandering when we see it. On the commute home, a programmer’s thoughts drift away from the sights and sounds of the subway car. At first she imagines the chicken she is brining for dinner. She can almost taste the thyme and rosemary when, suddenly, a line of code pops into her head. She plays with the code for a while, and then, smiling, remembers a joke she heard today . . . and so on. Clearly, the programmer’s mind is wandering. But what exactly makes her train of thought a case of mind-wandering? What precisely is mind-wandering?

Scientists in the empirical literature typically define mind-wandering as thought that is “task-unrelated” or “stimulus-independent,” or both. For example, Smallwood and Schooler define mind-wandering as “a shift in the contents of thought away from an ongoing task and/or from events in the external environment to self-generated thoughts and feelings” ( Smallwood & Schooler, 2015 , p. 488). This definition correctly identifies paradigm cases of mind-wandering. For example, the programmer’s wandering thoughts are unrelated to her ongoing task—commuting home—and to her external environment—the subway car.

Nevertheless, this definition abstracts away from a central feature of mind-wandering, namely, its dynamics ( Christoff, 2012 ; Irving, 2016 ). Wandering trains of thought unfold in a distinctive way over time. Experientially, the thoughts seem to drift freely from one topic (a line of code) to another one (a joke). Irving (2016) notes that the term “mind-wandering” reflects these dynamics: according to the Oxford English Dictionary (online), “to wander” means “to move hither and thither without fixed course or certain aim.” The preceding definition of mind-wandering, however, focuses only on individual mental states and seeks to determine whether their content is related to one’s task or environment. This focus tells us nothing about how trains of thought unfold over time. As we now argue, this definition of mind-wandering in static terms is unsatisfactory in two ways: it cannot differentiate between mind-wandering and other kinds of task-unrelated and stimulus-independent thought; and it cannot account for the fact that mind-wandering can be task-related.

Varieties of Task-Unrelated Thought

Current definitions of mind-wandering cannot distinguish it from depressive rumination, which is typically task-unrelated and stimulus-independent, but which has dynamics that fundamentally differ from that of mind-wandering ( Irving, 2016 ).

Rumination is “a mode of responding to distress that involves repetitively and passively focusing on symptoms of distress and on the possible causes and consequences of these symptoms. . . . People who are ruminating remain fixated on the problems and on their feelings about them” ( Nolen-Hoeksema, Wisco, & Lyubomirsky, 2008 ). Rumination is strongly associated with major depressive disorder, but also is found in the normal population ( Zetsche & Joormann, 2011 ). For example, a non-depressed teacher might ruminate about how to discipline a problem student.

Rumination is frequently task-unrelated and stimulus independent. For example, when a teacher ruminates about a problem student during her commute home, her thoughts are unrelated to her current task (commuting home) and perceptual environment (the subway train). Current researchers, therefore, classify rumination as a form of mind-wandering (e.g., Smallwood & Schooler, 2006 , 2015 ).

Rumination, however, seems antithetical to mind-wandering. Consider the ruminating teacher in contrast to the programmer whose mind is wandering. Both individuals have task-unrelated and stimulus-independent thoughts on their commute home. But the dynamics of their thoughts could hardly contrast more: whereas the teacher’s thoughts fixate on her problem student, the programmer’s thoughts drift from dinner to her computer code to a joke. In general, whereas rumination remains fixed on a single topic, mind-wandering drifts from one topic to the next. One has not wandered—“moved hither and thither”—if one has stayed on a single spot.

Mind-Wandering and Goal-Directed Thought: A Dilemma

Current definitions of mind-wandering face a dilemma concerning the relationship between mind-wandering and cognitive tasks. On the one hand, if we say that all stimulus-independent thinking is mind-wandering, then some mind-wandering will be task-related, because some stimulus-independent thinking is goal-directed. On the other hand, if we say that mind-wandering must be task-unrelated thinking, then we run afoul of empirical evidence that suggests that mind-wandering can be task-related. Let us explain each alternative and its problems in turn.

Suppose we define mind-wandering as any and all stimulus-independent thought. Smallwood and Schooler adopt this view, because they define mind-wandering as “a shift in the contents of thought away from an ongoing task and/ or from events in the external environment ” (2015, p. 488, emphasis added). According to the most restrictive conception in the literature, stimulus-independent mental states not only are non-perceptual states, but also are unrelated to any immediately present perceptual stimuli ( Schooler, Smallwood, Christoff, Handy, Reichle, & Sayette, 2011 ). For example, imagining or thinking about kicking the pigeon in front of you would not count as a stimulus-independent thought, but rather as a stimulus-related thought. Similarly, in a visual detection experiment, thinking “these pictures are flashing by too quickly,” would count as a stimulus-related thought, not a stimulus-independent one. Nevertheless, even this restricted specification of what is required for a thought to be stimulus-independent—that it be a non-perceptual state unrelated to any immediately present perceptual stimuli—classifies much of our goal-directed thought as stimulus-independent and hence (counterintuitively) as mind-wandering.

Consider a mathematician solving a proof in her head or a politician rehearsing a speech under her breath. Both women have thoughts unrelated to their external environments, so they count as mind-wandering, despite their thinking being goal-directed. The problem is that one’s thoughts cannot wander —“move hither and thither without fixed course or certain aim”—if they are directed by a goal. Indeed, theorists at least since Thomas Hobbes (1651) have defined mind-wandering by contrasting it to goal-directed cognition. In one of the first European philosophical discussions of mind-wandering, Hobbes states that thoughts that “wander . . . seem impertinent to each other, as in a Dream” (1651, p. 20). In contrast, he wrote that goal-directed thinking is “more constant; as being regulated by some desire, and designe. For the impression made by such things as wee desire, or feare, is strong and permanent, or, (if it cease for a time,) of quick return” (1651, pp. 20–21).

To distinguish mind-wandering from goal-directed thought, we could maintain that all mind-wandering is task-unrelated thought. According to this conception, neither the mathematician thinking about her proof nor the politician thinking about her speech is mind-wandering, because both are thinking about a task.

But now we face the second horn of the dilemma: Some mind-wandering is task-related ( Irving, 2016 ). Consider our vignette of a programmer whose mind is wandering on her commute home. Her thoughts drift to two personal goals—making dinner and writing code. Empirical evidence indicates that our minds often wander in this way to personal goals ( Klinger, 1999 ). Indeed, one study reported that at least 25% of a person’s wandering thoughts are about a “specific goal (defined as an objective or desired result that an individual endeavors to achieve)” ( Baird, Smallwood, & Schooler, 2011 , p. 1606). Another study found similar results with an experimentally induced goal. Participants were told that they would be quizzed on the names of US states after a “concentration task” ( Morsella, Ben-Zeev, Lanska, & Bargh, 2010 ). When participants had this goal, approximately 70% of their wandering thoughts were about geography (especially US state names). In contrast, the minds of participants in control conditions wandered to geography less than 10% of the time. This finding suggests that goals cause our minds to wander to goal-relevant information.

To see how such findings bear on the current definitions of mind-wandering, we must consider how “task-unrelated” is defined in the scientific literature. Laboratory studies define mind-wandering as thought that is unrelated to the experimental task (e.g., Christoff, Gordon, Smallwood, Smith, & Schooler, 2009 ). So far, so good: thoughts about personal goals such as making dinner are unrelated to the experimental task, and so correctly count as mind-wandering.

In studies of “real-world” mind-wandering outside the lab, however, “tasks” are operationally defined as whatever the person is currently doing . For example, participants are asked whether “my mind had wandered to something other than what I was doing ” ( Kane et al., 2007 , p. 616, emphasis added), or “are you thinking about something other than what you’re currently doing ?” ( Killingsworth & Gilbert, 2010 , p. 932, emphasis added).

Here is the problem. What you are doing often includes working toward the personal goals to which your mind wanders. For example, if we ask you, “what are you doing?” it would be natural for you to answer, “planning dinner” or “preparing for a test.” Therefore, rather than supposing that mind-wandering is task-unrelated thought, we could argue that individuals switch tasks when their minds begin to wander. According to this view, when the programmer’s mind wanders to computer code on the commute home, her task switches to coding from watching for her subway stop. Relative to the new task of coding, her thoughts about code count as task-related.

We can now bring the dilemma into full view. On the one hand, if we say that any and all stimulus-independent thought is mind-wandering, then we muddy the distinction between mind-wandering and goal-directed thinking. On the other hand, if we try to hold onto this distinction by supposing that mind-wandering must be task-unrelated thinking, then we contradict the empirical evidence that shows that task-related mind-wandering is not only possible but frequently actual.

Our diagnosis of the dilemma highlights the dynamics of mind-wandering. The distinction between mind-wandering versus goal-directed thinking does not concern whether mental states are task-unrelated or stimulus-independent. Rather, the distinction concerns how trains of thought unfold over time . When a mathematician solves a problem in her head, she maintains her attention on this problem for a prolonged period of time. In contrast, wandering thoughts “move hither and thither,” drifting between topics unchecked. Because current definitions of mind-wandering abstract away from its dynamics, they cannot distinguish mind-wandering from either rumination or goal-directed thinking. We now propose a theory that overcomes these limitations: mind-wandering is unguided thinking ( Irving, 2016 ).

Mind-Wandering Is Unguided Thinking

We define mind-wandering as unguided thinking. This definition depends on a particular concept of guidance taken from the philosophy of action. Thought or behavior is said to be guided when it is monitored and regulated as it unfolds over time ( Pacherie, 2008 ; Railton, 2006 ). Harry Frankfurt provides a classic philosophical explanation of guidance:

Behavior is purposive when its course is subject to adjustments which compensate for the effects of forces which would otherwise interfere with the course of the behavior. . . . This is merely another way of saying that their course is guided. ( Frankfurt, 1978 , pp. 159–160)

According to this account, “guidance” includes as part of its meaning a counterfactual aspect. To say that behavior is guided implies the following: Were one’s behavior to go off course or deviate from some standard—as a result, for example, of interfering forces—one would alter that behavior in order to bring it back on course. In other words, as Frankfurt states, guidance implies adjusting behavior to compensate for deviations. Thus the concept of guidance also includes a normative aspect: It implies the monitoring and correcting of behavior in relation to some norm or standard. For example, consider conversational interaction. In a conversation, you are guided to maintain a certain distance from your partner, for were your partner to stand too close to you, you would feel discomfited and drawn to step back ( Brownstein & Madva, 2012 ). In other words, your behavior is guided in the sense that it compensates for deviations from the (culturally specific) standards or norms of conversation. It follows that for behavior to be guided, there must be regulatory processes for bringing “deviant” behavior back on track.

We use this technical concept of guidance in order to specify what it means for thought to be guided. We propose that one’s thinking is guided only if one would feel pulled back to its topic, were one distracted from that topic. We also suppose that thinking can be guided in a variety of ways. Our thoughts can be guided back to goal-relevant information, as happens when we are goal-directed, or guided back to affectively salient information, as happens when we ruminate. Although different neurocognitive processes may underlie these two kinds of thinking, we argue that both kinds implement guidance in our technical sense.

Consider goal-directed thinking. In goal-directed thinking, one would feel pulled back to pursuing the goal were one to focus on information that seems irrelevant to it. Imagine a mathematician intently constructing a proof in a busy library. Her attentiveness manifests partly in how her attention is guided back from distractors. Were she to become momentarily distracted by students shuffling their papers, she would likely feel frustrated and pulled back to her work. Thus her mental activity is guided in its being regulated in relation to her goal.

We hypothesize that rumination also is guided. We predict that individuals who break away from their ruminative thoughts will feel pulled or drawn back to them. For thinking to be pulled or drawn back to a particular focus in this way is precisely for it to be counterfactually regulated and thus guided.

Our hypothesis that rumination is guided does not entail that it has the same psychological and neural profile as goal-directed attention (Table 8.1 ). On the contrary, as mentioned earlier, the genus “guided thought” allows for different species of guided thinking that are subserved by different brain processes. For example, top-down cognitive control processes appear to be largely responsible for the guidance of goal-directed thought (e.g., Corbetta & Shulman, 2002 ; Kane & Engle, 2002 ), whereas affective biases of attention and memory ( Todd, Cunningham, Anderson, & Thompson, 2012 ) likely play a strong role in one’s being guided toward ruminative thoughts. Furthermore, goal-directed attention is paradigmatically voluntary, whereas rumination typically is involuntary. The ruminator might complain, “I don’t want to think about distressing thoughts; they just keep pulling me back in.” Nevertheless, we propose that rumination and goal-directed attention are both guided in our technical sense: in either case, if individuals were mentally distracted from their current focus, they would feel their thoughts pulled back to it.

That goal-directed thought and rumination are both guided explains why both kinds of thinking are dynamically stable. Our thoughts remain fixed on a restricted set of information because they are guided to remain there.

In contrast, we define mind-wandering as unguided thinking ( Irving, 2016 ). Whereas a guided thinker would feel pulled back if she were distracted from her current focus, an unguided thinker wanders from one topic (dinner) to another (computer code); her mind drifts unchecked, with nothing to pull her back to a particular focus.

This lack of guidance explains why mind-wandering has an itinerant or unstable dynamics rather than a stable dynamics. Thoughts drift from topic to topic because nothing holds them in place. Thus our definition captures the dynamics of mind-wandering. Moreover, we provide a principled way to distinguish between different varieties of task-unrelated and stimulus-independent thought: in rumination, thoughts are guided to remain on the same topic and hence exhibit greater dynamical stability, whereas in mind-wandering, thoughts are unguided and hence exhibit greater dynamical instability.

Our account avoids the earlier-mentioned dilemma arising from the possibility of task-related mind-wandering. Recall that both wandering thoughts and goal-directed thoughts can be related to everyday tasks, such as planning dinner or writing computer code. Because of this possibility, current definitions of mind-wandering cannot properly distinguish it from goal-directed thinking. According to our account, the difference between them concerns how trains of thought are guided as they unfold over time. Goal-directed thinking is guided to remain on the same topic (e.g., writing code). Mind-wandering is unguided, so it is free to drift from one topic to the next. Its dynamics are unguided even when one’s mind wanders to a personal goal (such as writing computer code). The crucial point is that if one’s thoughts were to drift onward (e.g., to a joke one heard today), one would not be drawn back to a particular focus. 1

Our definition of mind-wandering as unguided thinking overcomes the limitations of previous definitions in the empirical literature. Our definition is based on an account wherein stretches of mind-wandering consist of trains of thought whose dynamics are unguided. This account, however, is not the only account of mind-wandering in the philosophical literature. We will now review two other accounts and critically assess them in relation to our own.

Mind-Wandering as Thought Lacking “Veto Control”

Thomas Metzinger (2013 ; see also Metzinger, Chapter 9 in this volume) proposes a theory of mind-wandering that helps to explain the relationship between mind-wandering and cases of goal-directed thinking, such as a mathematician constructing a proof. 2 Metzinger allows that mind-wandering can be goal-directed, and so his theory can accommodate the evidence that our minds frequently wander to our personal goals. Nevertheless, he maintains that mind-wandering differs from fully “autonomous” forms of goal-directed thinking, such as a mathematician consciously constructing a proof. In Metzinger’s view, goal-directed thinking is “mentally autonomous” only if one has the kind of cognitive control over one’s thoughts that he calls “veto control.”

The concept of “veto control” comes from cognitive science. It refers to the person’s ability to “withhold a . . . [behavior] 3 whose preparation and path towards execution has already begun” ( Filevich, Kühn, & Haggard, 2012 , p. 1108). Consider the following example in which you exercise veto control:

You are posting a letter, and are just about to release your grip on it and let it fall into the post box, when you suddenly get the feeling that you should check whether you put a stamp on the envelope. You tighten your grip and inspect the letter. ( Filevich et al., 2012 , p. 1108)

Note that you would have possessed veto control even if you had released the letter, because veto control requires only that you are able––and know that you are able––to suspend the relevant behavior ( Metzinger, 2013 , p. 4).

Metzinger argues that when our minds wander, we lack veto control over our thoughts. Thus he distinguishes mind-wandering from autonomous goal-directed thinking that we can suspend at will—for example, consciously constructing a math proof. In support of this view, Metzinger appeals to evidence that mind-wandering unfolds without meta-awareness ( Schooler et al., 2011 ). 4 “Meta-awareness” is defined as one’s explicit knowledge of the current contents of thought or one’s current conscious state ( Schooler, Smallwood, Christoff, Handy, Reichle, & Sayette, 2011 ). Thus meta-aware mental states are higher-order mental states that are about one’s ongoing or just past mental states. One example is a lucid dreamer’s meta-awareness that she is dreaming (see Windt and Voss, Chapter 29 in this volume). Another example is the sudden realization that your mind was wandering.

Metzinger’s argument has two premises. First, meta-awareness is necessary for veto control over a mental state or process ( Metzinger, 2013 , p. 3): A person cannot knowingly terminate something of which she is unaware. (Suppose I discover that you were not paying attention and I ask, “Why didn’t you stop your mind from wandering earlier?” You might reasonably respond, “I didn’t know my mind was wandering until just now.”) Second, Metzinger contends that whenever a person’s mind is wandering, she lacks meta-awareness of her wandering thoughts. From these two premises, it follows that people lack veto control over their wandering thoughts. Thus, Metzinger’s account suggests that mind-wandering can be defined as thinking that lacks meta-awareness and veto control.

The problem with this account is that the second premise—that mind-wandering always occurs without meta-awareness—is questionable. The evidence suggests that although mind-wandering sometimes occurs without meta-awareness, this is not always the case ( Christoff et al., 2009 ; Schooler, Smallwood, Christoff, Handy, Reichle, & Sayette, 2011 ; Smallwood & Schooler, 2006 ). Many studies of mind-wandering use self-reports to assess meta-awareness. Individuals who catch themselves mind-wandering or who report that their minds were wandering upon being probed are asked whether they were previously aware that their mind was wandering. For example, Smallwood and colleagues gave participants the following instructions in order to distinguish between aware (“tuning out”) versus unaware (“zoning out”) mind-wandering:

Tuning Out : Sometimes when your mind wanders, you are aware that your mind has drifted, but for whatever reason you still continue to read. This is what we refer to as “tuning out”––i.e., when your mind wanders and you know it all along. Zoning Out : Other times when your mind wanders, you don’t realize that your thoughts have drifted away from the text until you catch yourself. This is what we refer to as “zoning out”––i.e., when your mind wanders, but you don’t realize this until you catch it. ( Smallwood, McSpadden, & Schooler, 2007 , p. 533)

Across all conditions, Smallwood and colleagues found that tuning out occurred as frequently or more frequently than zoning out. Therefore, it may be that mind-wandering occurs at least as often with meta-awareness as without it (cf. Smallwood et al., 2004 ; Smallwood, Beach, Schooler, & Handy, 2008 ).

Metzinger argues that cases of apparently autonomous mind-wandering involve the mere “illusion of control” ( Metzinger, 2013 ; cf. Schooler et al., 2011 ), so he might question the reliability of reports of “tuning out” (mind-wandering with awareness). Nevertheless, tuning out and zoning out have different behavioral and neural profiles ( Schooler et al., 2011 ). For example, compared to tuning out, zoning out is associated with better reading comprehension ( Smallwood et al. 2008 ) and more activation of default network and executive regions ( Christoff et al. 2009 ) that are generally associated with mind-wandering ( Fox et al. 2015 ). It is not clear how to explain these differences, if reports of tuning out are entirely illusory.

Another limitation of Metzinger’s theory is that it neglects the dynamics of mind-wandering. Veto control and the presence versus absence of meta-awareness have no essential connection to how one’s thoughts unfold over time, according to his account. Therefore, his account cannot distinguish mind-wandering from rumination. Ruminators often seem to lack meta-awareness and hence veto control over their thoughts. For example, a commuter might fixate on her problems and distress without realizing that she has stopped watching for her subway stop. Because she is unaware that she has begun to ruminate, she cannot disengage from (veto) her distressing thoughts and bring herself back on task. Indeed, trait ruminators show impaired disengagement across a range of tasks ( Whitmer & Gotlib, 2013 ). This finding suggests that rumination frequently unfolds without veto control. Metzinger’s theory does not have the resources to explain how mind-wandering differs from this antithetical phenomenon of rumination.

Our account of mind-wandering as unguided thinking therefore has two advantages over Metzinger’s account ( Irving, 2016 , pp. 567–568). First, we allow that mind-wandering can unfold with or without meta-awareness. During cases of tuning out—“when your mind wanders and you know it all along” ( Smallwood et al., 2007 , p. 533)—we propose that you have meta-awareness of and thus veto control over your stream of unguided thoughts. Second, our account captures the dynamics of mind-wandering. Accordingly, we can explain how rumination and mind-wandering differ: Whereas the former is guided, the latter is not.

Mind-Wandering as Disunified Thinking

Peter Carruthers (2015) and Fabian Dorsch (2015) independently have proposed accounts of mind-wandering that rival the explanatory power of our own account. We focus on Carruthers’s theory, but our critical discussion applies to both philosophers. Carruthers discusses mind-wandering because it provides an apparent counterexample to his view that all thinking is active and goal-directed. He concedes that mind-wandering does “not seem, introspectively, to be active in nature. Sometimes one’s thoughts change direction for no apparent reason (especially when one’s mind is wandering)” ( Carruthers, 2015 , p. 166). Therefore, he must explain away the apparent difference between mind-wandering and goal-directed thought.

Carruthers explains away this apparent difference by drawing an analogy between mind-wandering and wandering around a garden: “Mind wandering is active, I suggest, in much the same sense that someone physically wandering around in a garden is active” ( Carruthers, 2015 , pp. 167–168). Dorsch (2015) draws a similar analogy between mind-wandering and physically wandering around a city. Both philosophers maintain that short stretches of physical and mental wandering are active. As you wander around a garden you might actively smell a rose or wish upon a dandelion. Similarly, you might actively plan dinner or write code while your mind wanders. Nevertheless, longer stretches of physical and mental wandering seem passive because no overarching goal unifies your thoughts. Given this point, Carruthers and Dorsch can explain away the apparent difference between mind-wandering and paradigm cases of goal-directed thought, such as a mathematician solving a proof in her head. Whereas the mathematician’s thoughts are all unified under a single goal (solving the proof), the mind-wanderer’s thoughts concern many goals (planning dinner, writing code, and so on). Thus mind-wandering seems more passive than goal-directed thought, though both are active when we look at them closely enough.

Carruthers’s and Dorsch’s discussions suggest that mind-wandering be defined as disunified thinking. A sequence of thoughts constitutes mind-wandering if and only if those thoughts are not unified under a common goal. This definition has major advantages. First, it captures the dynamics of mind-wandering: by definition, our wandering thoughts are dynamically unstable in the sense that they are not unified under a common goal. Second, this definition can account for the puzzling relationship between mind-wandering and goal-directed thought. On the one hand, short stretches of mind-wandering are related to tasks (such as preparing for a quiz), as the empirical evidence suggests. On the other hand, mind-wandering contrasts with goal-directed thinking because it is disunified.

Despite the advantages of this conception of mind-wandering, it has a problematic consequence, which we can bring out in the following example. Imagine someone who works for 10 minutes composing part of a lecture, then opens his web browser and responds to some emails for 6 minutes, and then looks outside the window, studying the pigeons across the street for 90 seconds. Furthermore, suppose that the person attentively pursues each goal. Nevertheless, no overarching goal unifies this whole sequence of thoughts, so they count as mind-wandering. Shifting from goal to goal in this way seems commonplace. Therefore, if we define mind-wandering as disunified thinking, most trains of goal-directed thinking will count as mind-wandering. But then it seems that Carruthers and Dorsch have not captured the difference between mind-wandering and goal-directed thinking at all.

A deeper problem lurks in the vicinity. Whether thinking counts as disunified, and thus as mind-wandering, depends on the scale of observation or how far we zoom out (Figure 8.1 ). Suppose we examine the person’s thoughts in the previous example. In the first five minutes, his attention is wholly guided by the goal of composing his lecture. During that interval, his attention is unified and his mind is not wandering. But if we zoom out to a seventeen-minute interval, we find thoughts about three separate goals—composing a lecture, writing emails, and watching pigeons. From this broader perspective, his attention is disunified and his mind is wandering. The problem is that we lack principled reasons for deciding how far to zoom out, and therefore we lack principled reasons for saying whether his mind is wandering at any given point in time.

Disunity and zoom.

This consequence undermines the scientific methods we use to study mind-wandering. These methods require that we be able to specify when the mind is wandering versus when it is not, so that we can study the distinctive features of MIND-WANDERING (such as ITS contents and neural correlates) versus other kinds of THINKING. For example, Christoff et al. (2009) compared neural activation when individuals were concentrating on a task versus mentally wandering away from it. If we define mind-wandering as disunified thinking, then we cannot use these methods, because if we zoom out, then the on-task thoughts are probably going to count as wandering thoughts. No methodological innovation could solve this problem. In other words, given the definition of mind-wandering as disunified thinking, there will be no principled way to distinguish mind-wandering from goal-directed thought. Therefore, this definition is a non-starter for the cognitive science of mind-wandering.

In contrast, our definition of mind-wandering as unguided thought does not face these problems. We provide a principled way to distinguish goal-directed and wandering thought: The former is guided; the latter is not. Therefore, our definition is preferable on conceptual grounds as well as being more amenable to empirical investigation.

Psychologists, cognitive neuroscientists, and philosophers should be partners in the scientific investigation of mind-wandering. The challenges facing this young field are not only empirical, but also conceptual and theoretical. Our chapter begins with a philosophical critique of the most widely accepted definitions of mind-wandering in cognitive psychology. This critique stems from the idea that mind-wandering is fundamentally dynamic. Our definition uses the technical philosophical notion of “guidance” to capture its dynamics. Compared to the other extant philosophical definitions, our definition of mind-wandering as unguided thought is not only more theoretically defensible, but also more scientifically tractable. Putting this definition to work in cognitive science will require close collaborations with psychologists and cognitive neuroscientists. For example, difficult questions remain about how to measure the dynamics of mind-wandering ( Christoff, 2012 ) and how to relate the philosophical notion of guidance to dynamical neural networks and psychological processes ( Christoff, Irving, Fox, Spreng, & Andrews-Hanna, 2016 ). The path forward requires that psychologists, cognitive neuroscientists, and philosophers work together to advance our understanding of mind-wandering.

One might worry that our view characterizes mind-wandering as too disordered . Although mind-wandering is certainly less stable than goal-directed or ruminative thought, our wandering thoughts are not entirely random: for example, our minds often wander to personal goals and concerns (as noted earlier) and between associated thoughts. For similar reasons, we elsewhere propose a neuroscientific model on which the dynamics of mind-wandering are somewhat constrained, albeit less so than goal-directed or ruminative thoughts ( Christoff, Irving, et al., 2016 ). Fortunately, our philosophical model of mind-wandering is compatible with the presence of dynamic constraints on mind-wandering. This is because guidance is not the only way that thought can be constrained. Mind-wandering can be probabilistically constrained, in that we often think of particular things (e.g., close associations, personal goals and concerns). Yet we contend that when the mind wanders, no guidance mechanism holds our thoughts in place; when the mind wanders to unusual ideas, or from one topic to another, nothing pulls us back. See Irving (2016) for an in-depth discussion of the different types of constraints on thought, including those that are present and absent during mind-wandering.

Much of the material for this section is adapted from Irving (2016) .

Filevich and colleagues originally defined “veto control” as the ability to “withhold an action.” We have changed the definition, replacing “action” with “behavior,” because veto control arguably is necessary for action (as opposed to mere movement). In that case, defining “veto control” as the ability to withhold an action would trivially imply that one never lacks veto control.

Thus Metzinger expands upon Smallwood and Schooler’s (2006) thesis that mind-wandering differs from goal-directed thought because the former always begins without meta-awareness.

Baird, B. , Smallwood, J. , & Schooler, J. W. ( 2011 ). Back to the future: Autobiographical planning and the functionality of mind-wandering.   Consciousness and Cognition , 20 (4), 1604–1611. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2011.08.007

Google Scholar

Brownstein, M. , & Madva, A. ( 2012 ). The normativity of automaticity.   Mind & Language , 27 (4), 410–434.

Callard, F. , Smallwood, J. , Golchert, J. , & Margulies, D. S. ( 2013 ). The era of the wandering mind? Twenty-first century research on self-generated mental activity.   Frontiers in Psychology , 4 (891).

Carruthers, P. ( 2015 ). The centered mind: What the science of working memory shows us about the nature of human thought . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Google Preview

Christoff, K. ( 2012 ). Undirected thought: Neural determinants and correlates.   Brain Research , 1428 , 51–59.

Christoff, K. , Gordon, A. M. , Smallwood, J. , Smith, R. , & Schooler, J. W. ( 2009 ). Experience sampling during fMRI reveals default network and executive system contributions to mind wandering.   Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences , 106 (21), 8719–8724.

Christoff, K. , Irving, Z. C. , Fox, K. C. R. , Spreng, R. N. , & Andrews-Hanna, J. R. ( 2016 ). Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: A dynamic framework.   Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 17 , 718–731.

Corbetta, M. , & Shulman, G. L. ( 2002 ). Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in the brain.   Nature Reviews Neuroscience , 3 (3), 201–15. http://doi.org/10.1038/nrn755

Dorsch, F. ( 2015 ). Focused daydreaming and mind-wandering.   Review of Philosophy and Psychology , 6 (4), 791–813.

Filevich, E. , Kühn, S. , & Haggard, P. ( 2012 ). Intentional inhibition in human action: The power of no.   Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews , 36 (4), 1107–1118.

Fox, K. C. R. , Spreng, R. N. , Ellamil, M. , Andrews-Hanna, J. R. , & Christoff, K. ( 2015 ). The wandering brain: Meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging studies of mind-wandering and related spontaneous thought processes.   NeuroImage , 111 (1), 611–621.

Frankfurt, H. ( 1978 ). The problem of action.   American Philosophical Quarterly , 15 (2), 157–162.

Hobbes, T. ( 1651 ). Leviathan, or the matter, forme and power of a commonwealth ecclesiasticall and civil . New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Irving, Z. C. ( 2016 ). Mind-wandering is unguided attention: Accounting for the “purposeful” wanderer.   Philosophical Studies , 173 (2), 547–571.

Kane, M. J. , Brown, L. H. , McVay, J. C. , Silvia, P. J. , Myin-Germeys, I. , & and Thomas R. Kwapil. ( 2007 ). For whom the mind wanders, and when: An experience-sampling study of working memory and executive control in daily life.   Psychological Science , 18 (7), 614–621.

Kane, M. J. , & Engle, R. W. ( 2002 ). The role of prefrontal cortex in working-memory capacity, executive attention, and general fluid intelligence: An individual-differences perspective.   Psychonomic Bulletin & Review , 9 (4), 637–671. http://doi.org/10.3758/BF03196323

Killingsworth, M. a, & Gilbert, D. T. ( 2010 ). A wandering mind is an unhappy mind.   Science (New York, N.Y. ), 330 (6006), 932. http://doi.org/10.1126/science.1192439

Klinger, E. ( 1999 ). Thought flow: Properties and mechanisms underlying shifts in content. In J. A. Singer and P. Salovey (Eds.), At play in the fields of consciousness: Essays in honor of Jerome L. Singer (pp. 29–50). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Metzinger, T. ( 2013 ). The myth of cognitive agency.   Frontiers in Psychology , 4 (931).

Metzinger, T. ( 2015 ). M-Autonomy.   Journal of Consciousness Studies , 22 (11–12), 270–302.

Morsella, E. , Ben-Zeev, A. , Lanska, M. , & Bargh, J. A. ( 2010 ). The spontaneous thoughts of the night: How future tasks breed intrusive cognitions.   Social Cognition , 28 (5), 641–650. http://doi.org/10.1521/soco.2010.28.5.641

Nolen-Hoeksema, S. , Wisco, B. E. , & Lyubomirsky, S. ( 2008 ). Rethinking rumination.   Perspectives on Psychological Science , 3 , 400–424.

Pacherie, E. ( 2008 ). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework.   Cognition , 107 (1), 179–217. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2007.09.003

Railton, P. ( 2006 ). Normative guidance.   Oxford Studies in Metaethics , 1 , 3–34.

Schooler, J. W. , Smallwood, J. , Christoff, K. , Handy, T. C. , Reichle, E. D. , & Sayette, M. A. ( 2011 ). Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind.   Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15 (7), 319–326. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2011.05.006

Smallwood, J. , Beach, E. , Schooler, J. W. , & Handy, T. C. ( 2008 ). Going AWOL in the brain: Mind wandering reduces cortical analysis of external events. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience , 20 (3), 458–469.

Smallwood, J. , Davies, J. B. , Heim, D. , Finnigan, F. , Sudberry, M. , O’Connor, R. , & Obonsawin, M. ( 2004 ). Subjective experience and the attentional lapse: Task engagement and disengagement during sustained attention.   Consciousness and Cognition , 13 (4), 657–690.

Smallwood, J. , McSpadden, M. , & Schooler, J. W. ( 2007 ). The lights are on but no one’s home: Meta-awareness and the decoupling of attention when the mind wanders.   Psychonomic Bulletin & Review , 14 (3), 527–533. http://doi.org/10.3758/BF03194102

Smallwood, J. , & Schooler, J. W. ( 2006 ). The restless mind.   Psychological Bulletin , 132 (6), 946–958.

Smallwood, J. , & Schooler, J. W. ( 2015 ). The science of mind wandering: Empirically navigating the stream of consciousness.   Annual Review of Psychology , 66 , 487–518.

Sutton, J. ( 2010 ). Carelessness and inattention: Mind-wandering and the physiology of fantasy from Locke to Hume. In C. T. Wolfe & O. Gal (Eds.), The body as object and instrument of knowledge (pp. 243–263). New York: Springer.

Thompson, E. ( 2015 ). Waking, dreaming, being: New light on the self and consciousness from neuroscience, meditation, and philosophy . New York: Columbia University Press.

Todd, R. M. , Cunningham, W. A. , Anderson, A. K. , & Thompson, E. ( 2012 ). Affect-biased attention as emotion regulation.   Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 16 (7), 365–372.

Whitmer, A. J. , & Gotlib, I. H. ( 2013 ). An attentional scope model of rumination.   Psychological Bulletin , 139 (5), 1036–1061. http://doi.org/10.1037/a0030923

Zetsche, U. , & Joormann, J. ( 2011 ). Components of interference control predict depressive symptoms and rumination cross-sectionally and at six months follow-up.   Journal of Behavior Therapy and Experimental Psychiatry , 42 (1), 65–73. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbtep.2010.06.001

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

A woman working at a table crowded with books looks away from her laptop screen.

It’s normal for your mind to wander. Here’s how to maximise the benefits

mind wandering significato

Psychology researcher, Bond University

mind wandering significato

Associate Professor in Psychology, Bond University

Disclosure statement

The authors do not work for, consult, own shares in or receive funding from any company or organisation that would benefit from this article, and have disclosed no relevant affiliations beyond their academic appointment.

Bond University provides funding as a member of The Conversation AU.

View all partners

Have you ever found yourself thinking about loved ones during a boring meeting? Or going over the plot of a movie you recently watched during a drive to the supermarket?

This is the cognitive phenomenon known as “ mind wandering ”. Research suggests it can account for up to 50% of our waking cognition (our mental processes when awake) in both western and non-western societies .

So what can help make this time productive and beneficial?

Mind wandering is not daydreaming

Mind wandering is often used interchangeably with daydreaming. They are both considered types of inattention but are not the same thing.

Mind wandering is related to a primary task, such as reading a book, listening to a lecture, or attending a meeting. The mind withdraws from that task and focuses on internally generated, unrelated thoughts.

On the other hand, daydreaming does not involve a primary, active task. For example, daydreaming would be thinking about an ex-partner while travelling on a bus and gazing out the window. Or lying in bed and thinking about what it might be like to go on a holiday overseas.

If you were driving the bus or making the bed and your thoughts diverted from the primary task, this would be classed as mind wandering.

A woman sits by a window gazing out onto trees outside.

The benefits of mind wandering

Mind wandering is believed to play an important role in generating new ideas , conclusions or insights (also known as “aha! moments”). This is because it can give your mind a break and free it up to think more creatively.

This type of creativity does not always have to be related to creative pursuits (such as writing a song or making an artwork). It could include a new way to approach a university or school assignment or a project at work. Another benefit of mind wandering is relief from boredom, providing the opportunity to mentally retreat from a monotonous task.

For example, someone who does not enjoy washing dishes could think about their upcoming weekend plans while doing the chore. In this instance, mind wandering assists in “passing the time” during an uninteresting task.

Mind wandering also tends to be future-oriented. This can provide an opportunity to reflect upon and plan future goals, big or small. For example, what steps do I need to take to get a job after graduation? Or, what am I going to make for dinner tomorrow?

A person washes a glass in a sink, with dirty dishes on the side.

Read more: Alpha, beta, theta: what are brain states and brain waves? And can we control them?

What are the risks?

Mind wandering is not always beneficial, however. It can mean you miss out on crucial information. For example, there could be disruptions in learning if a student engages in mind wandering during a lesson that covers exam details. Or an important building block for learning.

Some tasks also require a lot of concentration in order to be safe. If you’re thinking about a recent argument with a partner while driving, you run the risk of having an accident.

That being said, it can be more difficult for some people to control their mind wandering. For example, mind wandering is more prevalent in people with ADHD.

Read more: How your brain decides what to think

What can you do to maximise the benefits?

There are several things you can do to maximise the benefits of mind wandering.

  • be aware : awareness of mind wandering allows you to take note of and make use of any productive thoughts. Alternatively, if it is not a good time to mind wander it can help bring your attention back to the task at hand

A man writes in a diary.

context matters : try to keep mind wandering to non-demanding tasks rather than demanding tasks. Otherwise, mind wandering could be unproductive or unsafe. For example, try think about that big presentation during a car wash rather than when driving to and from the car wash

content matters : if possible, try to keep the content positive. Research has found , keeping your thoughts more positive, specific and concrete (and less about “you”), is associated with better wellbeing. For example, thinking about tasks to meet upcoming work deadlines could be more productive than ruminating about how you felt stressed or failed to meet past deadlines.

  • Consciousness
  • Daydreaming
  • Concentration
  • Mind wandering

mind wandering significato

Biocloud Project Manager - Australian Biocommons

mind wandering significato

Director, Defence and Security

mind wandering significato

Opportunities with the new CIEHF

mind wandering significato

School of Social Sciences – Public Policy and International Relations opportunities

mind wandering significato

Deputy Editor - Technology

Greater Good Science Center • Magazine • In Action • In Education

Mind & Body Articles & More

How to focus a wandering mind, new research reveals what happens in a wandering mind—and sheds light on the cognitive and emotional benefits of increased focus..

We’ve all been there. You’re slouched in a meeting or a classroom, supposedly paying attention, but your mind has long since wandered off, churning out lists of all the things you need to do—or that you could be doing if only you weren’t stuck here…

Suddenly you realize everyone is looking your way expectantly, waiting for an answer. But you’re staring blankly, grasping at straws to make a semi-coherent response. The curse of the wandering mind!

But don’t worry—you’re not alone. In fact, a recent study by Matthew Killingsworth and Daniel Gilbert sampled over 2,000 adults during their day-to-day activities and found that 47 percent of the time, their minds were not focused on what they were currently doing. Even more striking, when people’s minds were wandering, they reported being less happy.

mind wandering significato

This suggests it might be good to find ways to reduce these mental distractions and improve our ability to focus. Ironically, mind-wandering itself can help strengthen our ability to focus, if leveraged properly. This can be achieved using an age-old skill: meditation. Indeed, a new wave of research reveals what happens in our brains when our minds wander—and sheds light on the host of cognitive and emotional benefits that come with increased focus.

What happens in the wandering mind?

For something that happens so often, what do we really know about this process of mind-wandering?

For thousands of years, contemplative practices such as meditation have provided a means to look inward and investigate our mental processes. It may seem surprising, but mind-wandering is actually a central element of focused attention (FA) meditation. In this foundational style of meditation, the practitioner is instructed to keep her attention on a single object, often the physical sensations of breathing. 

Sounds simple enough, but it’s much easier said than done. Try it for a few minutes and see what happens. 

If you’re like most people, before long your attention will wander away into rumination, fantasy, analyzing, planning. At some point, you might realize that your mind is no longer focused on the breath. With this awareness, you proceed to disengage from the thought that had drawn your mind away, and steer your attention back to your breath. A few moments later, the cycle will likely repeat.

At first it might seem like the tendency toward mind-wandering would be a problem for the practice of FA meditation, continually derailing your attention from the “goal” of keeping your mind on the breath. 

However, the practice is really meant to highlight this natural trajectory of the mind, and in doing so, it trains your attention systems to become more aware of the mental landscape at any given moment, and more adept at navigating it. With repeated practice, it doesn’t take so long to notice that you’ve slipped into some kind of rumination or daydream. It also becomes easier to drop your current train of thought and return your focus to the breath. Those who practice say that thoughts start to seem less “sticky”—they don’t have such a hold on you.

As a neuroscientist and meditator, I’d long been fascinated with what might be happening in my brain when I meditate. Being familiar with both subjective, first-person meditative practice and objective, third-person scientific research, I wondered what would happen if I put these two modes of investigation together. Could I get a more fine-grained picture of how this process works in the brain by leveraging the experience of these cognitive shifts during meditation?

I started by considering the default mode network, a set of brain areas that tend to increase in activity when we’re not actively engaged in anything else—in other words, when our minds tend to wander. Maybe it was this default mode network that kept barging in during my meditation, interfering with my ability to keep my attention focused. And maybe this network was what I was learning to “tune down” by practicing over and over. I wondered if I could test this scientifically.

Supported by funding from the Mind & Life Institute , and with the help of colleagues at Emory University, I started to test which brain areas were related to meditation. We asked meditators to focus on their breath while we scanned their brains: whenever they realized their minds had been wandering, they’d press a button. Then they would return their focus to the breath as usual, and the practice would continue. As they did so, we collected MRI data showing which brain regions were active before, during, or after the button press that corresponded to various mental states.

The study, published in the journal NeuroImage , found that, indeed, during periods of mind-wandering, regions of the brain’s default mode network were activated. Then when participants became aware of this mind-wandering, brain regions related to the detection of salient or relevant events came online. After that, areas of the executive brain network took over, re-directing and maintaining attention on the chosen object. And all of this occurred within 12 seconds around those button presses.

Looking at activity in these brain networks this way suggests that when you catch your mind wandering, you are going through a process of recognizing, and shifting out of, default mode processing by engaging numerous attention networks. Understanding the way the brain alternates between focused and distracted states has implications for a wide variety of everyday tasks. For example, when your mind wandered off in that meeting, it might help to know you’re slipping into default mode—and you can deliberately bring yourself back to the moment. That’s an ability that can improve with training.

The benefits of building focus

What are other practical implications of this knowledge? Recent behavioral research shows that practicing meditation trains various aspects of attention . Studies show that meditation training not only improves working memory and fluid intelligence , but even standardized test scores . 

It’s not surprising—this kind of repeated mental exercise is like going to the gym, only you’re building your brain instead of your muscles. And mind-wandering is like the weight you add to the barbell—you need some “resistance” to the capacity you’re trying to build. Without mind-wandering to derail your attempts to remain focused, how could you train the skills of watching your mind and controlling your attention?

In our study, we also wanted to look at the effects of lifetime meditation experience on brain activity. In agreement with a growing number of studies, we found that experience mattered—those who were more experienced meditators had different levels of brain activity in the relevant networks. This suggests that their brains may have changed due to repeated practice, a process called neuroplasticity. 

One brain area stood out in this analysis: the medial prefrontal cortex, a part of the default mode network that is particularly related to self-focused thoughts , which make up a good portion of mind-wandering content. It turns out that experienced meditators deactivated this region more quickly after identifying mind-wandering than people who hadn’t meditated as much—suggesting they might be better at releasing distracting thoughts, like a re-hash of a personal To Do list or some slight they suffered at work yesterday.

In a follow-up study, we found that these same participants had greater coherence between activity in the medial prefrontal cortex and brain areas that allow you to disengage attention . This means that the brain regions for attentional disengagement have greater access to the brain regions underlying the distraction, possibly making it easier to disengage. Other findings support this idea—more experienced meditators have increased connectivity between default mode and attention brain regions, and less default mode activity while meditating.

This might explain how it feels easier to “drop” thoughts as you become more experienced in meditation—and thus better able to focus. Thoughts become less sticky because your brain gets re-wired to be better at recognizing and disengaging from mind-wandering. And if you’ve ever struggled with rumination—re-living a negative experience over and over, or stressing (unproductively) about an upcoming event—you can appreciate how being able to let go of your thoughts could be a huge benefit. 

Indeed, the Killingsworth and Gilbert study I mentioned earlier found that when people’s minds were wandering, they tended to be less happy , presumably because our thoughts often tend towards negative rumination or stress. That’s why mindfulness meditation has become an increasingly important treatment of mental health difficulties like depression , anxiety , post-traumatic stress disorder , and even sexual dysfunction .

More on Mindfulness & Mind-Wandering

Learn more about how mind-wandering can make you unhappy

How mindful are you? Take our quiz!

Watch Jon Kabat-Zinn talk about mindfulness .

Reading all this might make you think that we’d be better off if we could live our lives in a constant state of laser-like, present moment focus. But a wandering mind isn’t all bad. Not only can we leverage it to build focus using FA meditation, but the capacity to project our mental stream out of the present and imagine scenarios that aren’t actually happening is hugely evolutionarily valuable, which may explain why it’s so prominent in our mental lives. These processes allow for creativity, planning, imagination, memory—capacities that are central not only to our survival, but also to the very essence of being human.

The key, I believe, is learning to become aware of these mental tendencies and to use them purposefully, rather than letting them take over. Meditation can help with that.

So don’t beat yourself up the next time you find yourself far away from where your mind was supposed to be. It’s the nature of the mind to wander. Use it as an opportunity to become more aware of your own mental experience. But you may still want to return to the present moment—so you can come up with an answer to that question everyone is waiting for.

About the Author

Wendy hasenkamp.

Wendy Hasenkamp, Ph.D., is a neuroscientist and Senior Scientific Officer at the Mind & Life Institute.

You May Also Enjoy

Better Eating through Mindfulness

This article — and everything on this site — is funded by readers like you.

Become a subscribing member today. Help us continue to bring “the science of a meaningful life” to you and to millions around the globe.

U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Front Psychol

The impacts of mind-wandering on flow: Examining the critical role of physical activity and mindfulness

Yu-qin deng.

1 Institute of Sports Science, Nantong University, Nantong, China

2 School of Psychology, Shanghai University of Sport, Shanghai, China

Xinyan Zheng

3 School of Kinesiology, Shanghai University of Sport, Shanghai, China

Xiaochun Wang

Chenglin zhou, associated data.

The raw data supporting the conclusions of this article will be made available by the authors, without undue reservation.

Individuals with mind-wandering experience their attention decoupling from their main task at hand while others with flow experience fully engage in their task with the optimum experience. There seems to be a negative relationship between mind-wandering and flow. However, it remains unclear to what extent mind-wandering exerts an impact on flow. And it is also elusive whether physical activity and mindfulness, which are as important factors that affected individuals’ attentional control and psychological health, are beneficial in explaining the association between mind-wandering and flow. The current study investigated the relationship between mind-wandering and flow, and the potential mediation effects of physical activity and mindfulness in this association.

A cross-sectional exploratory study design, including multiple scales such as the Mind-Wandering Questionnaire (MWQ), the International Physical Activity Questionnaire Short Form (IPAQ), Mindfulness Attention and Awareness Scale (MAAS), and the Short Dispositional Flow Scale (S-DFS) was applied. Descriptive statistics and bivariate correlation coefficients were applied in the analysis of these data. A multiple mediation model was used to examine the relationships between mind-wandering, flow, physical activity, and mindfulness.

Mind-wandering was inversely associated with physical activity, mindfulness and flow, respectively; and flow was positively related to physical activity and mindfulness, respectively. Moreover, multiple mediation results demonstrated that physical activity and mindfulness, respectively, mediated the relationship between mind-wandering and flow.

These findings are helpful to understand how our minds attend to the present moment, and the crucial roles of physical activity and mindfulness in the association between mind-wandering and flow. An implication of these is the possibility that the effective strategies aimed at enhancing both the levels of physical activity and mindfulness are needed to reduce the negative impact of mind-wandering on flow.

Introduction

Mind-wandering is a ubiquitous phenomenon encompassing specific aspects of consciousness in which the mind loses focus on the present moment and begins to generate spontaneous thoughts ( Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). Abundant experimental evidence has demonstrated that mind-wandering has detrimental effects on tasks that require undivided attention (i.e., reading comprehension and tests of cognitive performance), and self-reported depressive mind ( Mooneyham and Schooler, 2013 ; Deng et al., 2014 ). On the other hand, mind-wandering contributes to creativity and innovation, as it enables the establishment of new connections between previous and potential experiences ( Mooneyham and Schooler, 2013 ). Self-generated thoughts can be conceptualized as involving a conscious state of internal attention decoupled from current perception (i.e., not based on perceptual input) ( Schooler et al., 2011 ). They are dynamic, and individual can intermittently monitor their content explicitly through meta-awareness ( Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). According to the Context Regulation Hypothesis, mind-wandering can be regulated to generate optimal cognition to meet external demands (i.e., task performance) ( Smallwood and Andrews-Hanna, 2013 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ; Thomson et al., 2015 ; Smallwood et al., 2021 ). Thus, it is considered to be a form of adaptive attention control facilitating adjustment to the environment or creative problem solving ( Kam et al., 2013 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). Given the costs and benefits of mind-wandering, the identification of its effects mind-wandering and exploration of its relationships with other variables are important. Our previous study demonstrated that self-control and mindfulness sequentially mediate the relationship between mind-wandering and metacognition ( Deng et al., 2019 ). The finding makes an important contribution to our understanding of the characteristics of information processing in our mind. However, more research is required to determine the effects of mind-wandering, and to provide a theoretical basis for the understanding of psychological adjustment.

Unlike mind-wandering, flow is viewed as a special type of attention in which individuals are fully attuned to the present moment to attain the greatest effectiveness ( Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ). A recent study showed that positively perceived feedback boosted billiard players’ flow experience, enabling them to more mindfully and flexibly self-regulate their focus on the present moment, with reduced attention to distractions that could impede their performance. Thus, flow, as a subjective experience of “deep and effortless concentration,” entails reduced mind-wandering and increased mindfulness ( Marty-Dugas and Smilek, 2018 ; Lambert and Csikszentmihalyi, 2019 ). However, the mechanisms underlying the negative relationship between flow and mind-wandering remain unclear. According to the attentional model, the experience of flow involves the narrowing of attention and enhancement of moment-to-moment orientation, whereas mind-wandering involves the broadening of attention and reduction of moment-to-moment orientation ( Dane, 2011 ; Dust, 2015 ); both states thus rely on attention control. Mind-wandering has been referred to as the “dynamic redistribution of attention resources,” in which individuals’ attention drifts away from external tasks to ongoing internal thoughts ( Smallwood and Andrews-Hanna, 2013 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ; Thomson et al., 2015 ; Smallwood et al., 2021 ). Individuals with better attention control tend to have enhanced meta-awareness and regulation of self-generated thoughts ( Schooler et al., 2011 ). Flow leads to the efficient allocation of the limited attentional resources, resulting in effortless concentration, and improvement of task performance ( Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ; Harris et al., 2017 ). Few studies, however, have explored how spontaneous thoughts influence the flow experience.

Mind-wandering and flow both enhance creativity. Especially during the performance of undemanding tasks, mind-wandering allows for the generation of more spontaneous thoughts and ebb and flow of attention ( Schooler et al., 2014 ; Williams et al., 2018 ; Zedelius and Schooler, 2020 ); similarly, greater flow experiences have been found to be related significantly to greater degrees of creativity ( MacDonald et al., 2006 ; Schutte and Malouff, 2020 ). Thus, mind-wandering might be expected to predict flow, but more research is needed to examine this potential relationship and its mediators. Mind-wandering occurs with high frequency, occupying about half of the individuals’ waking hours, and is thus, a prevalent and important experience in daily life ( Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). On the other hand, flow is rarely attained, but plays a beneficial role in routine task performance ( Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ). Individuals experiencing flow tend to effectively cope with and enjoy the task at hand, and ultimately to have improved their quality of life. Knowledge of the relationship between mind-wandering and flow, and the mechanisms underlying it would provide insight on how to make spontaneous thoughts more positive and adaptive, have more optimal experiences in our daily lives, and understand the characteristics of our mental activity more deeply.

Based on the previous research, mindfulness may be involved in the association between mind-wandering and flow. Mindfulness, as the present-being experience that induces self-regulation of attention and awareness ( Karunamuni and Weerasekera, 2019 ) has beneficial effects on attentional control and psychological health ( Karunamuni and Weerasekera, 2019 ; Prakash et al., 2020 ). The Mindful Awareness Attention Scale (MAAS) has been developed for the assessment of dispositional mindfulness. MAAS scores correlate negatively with multiple self-reported mind-wandering, clarifying that these constructs are opposite ( Mrazek et al., 2012 ; Stawarczyk et al., 2012 ). Individuals with lower MAAS scores are more likely to report higher frequencies of mind-wandering during driving or the performance of demanding cognitive tasks ( Burdett et al., 2016 ; Ju and Lien, 2018 ). Conversely, greater mindfulness correlates with less mind-wandering and a greater frequency of flow ( Deng et al., 2014 ; Marty-Dugas and Smilek, 2018 ; Lambert and Csikszentmihalyi, 2019 ; Xie, 2021 ). Mindfulness and flow are both characterized by the strong focus of attention at the present moment ( Wright et al., 2006 ; Šimleša et al., 2018 ). Through the facilitation of attentional control, mindfulness can help individuals be more aware of current thoughts and goal-directed actions, and guide them from mind-wandering to a focus on the current task ( Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ; Prakash et al., 2020 ). Consequently, mindfulness may mediate the relationship between mind-wandering and flow, but further research is needed to test this hypothesis.

Physical activity has beneficial effects on attentional control and psychological health ( Plante and Rodin, 1990 ; Winneke et al., 2012 ; Fortier and Morgan, 2021 ), and has been shown to be associated closely with mind-wandering and flow. Current spontaneous thoughts have been demonstrated to be significantly associated with moderate-to-vigorous physical activity ( Fanning et al., 2016 ) while physical activity has been shown to influence the ability to exert flexible cognitive control, which is closely related to the mind-wandering ( Buckley et al., 2014 ). Higher levels of physical activity are also more likely to contribute to the experience of flow, especially in athletes and inactive individuals ( Jackson and Eklund, 2002 ; Elbe et al., 2010 ). Among athletes, greater task orientation (reflecting clearer goal and sensitive to control over the activity) has been shown to be related closely to flow ( Stavrou et al., 2015 ). In addition, individuals engaging in recreational physical activity have been found to experience more flow-like episodes correlated with greater situational involvement; these experiences and feelings are enjoyable ( Decloe et al., 2009 ). Inactive individuals have been found to experience flow after long-term physical activity interventions ( Elbe et al., 2010 ). All of these findings imply that physical activity could be as important factors in the flow experience. Thus, physical activity may mediate the association between mind-wandering and flow.

The current study was conducted to investigate correlations among mind-wandering, mindfulness, physical activity, and flow, and to examine the mediating effects of mindfulness and physical activity on the relationships between mind-wandering and flow. The hypothesis was that mind-wandering would be related to lower levels of mindfulness and physical activity, which in turn would be related to lower levels of flow. A multiple mediator analysis would then be performed to compare the different mediating effects of mindfulness and physical activity on the associations between mind-wandering and flow.

Materials and methods

Participants.

The present research was approved by relevant institutional ethics committees. Anonymous, self-report questionnaires (described later) were distributed to a sample of 465 healthy college students in China. The participants completed the questionnaires with a pen. A total of 36 participants did not completely fill in these measurements. Finally, data collected from 429 Chinese college students (103 females; mean age = 19.62 years, SD = 1.30 years) was included in the final data analysis. Within the sample of undergraduate students, 4% of them reported their major in applied psychology; 7% of them in sports training; 10.3% of them in national traditional sports; 20.2% of them in social sports guidance and management and 58.5% of them in physical education.

Mind-wandering

The 5-item Mind-Wandering Questionnaire (MWQ), which is on a 6-point Likert scale ranging from 1 (almost never) to 6 (almost always), was used to measure the levels of mind-wandering ( Mrazek et al., 2013 ). All of these items were averaged as the MWQ score, with greater scores indicating higher levels of mind-wandering (e.g., “I mind-wander during lectures of presentations”). The Chinese version of MWQ has been validated ( Luo et al., 2016 ). In Chinese sample, the fit indices for confirmatory factor analysis of the scale were as follows: χ 2 / df = 3.6, comparative fit index (CFI) = 0.98, the Tucker–Lewis index (TLI) = 0.93, root mean square error of approximation (RMSEA) = 0.06, standardized root mean square residual (SRMR) = 0.03, indicating MWQ had an adequate model fit. The Cronbach’s reliability (0.74) for the Chinese sample was satisfactory.

Mindfulness

Dispositional mindful awareness was assessed using Mindfulness Attention and Awareness Scale (MAAS), which contains 15 items and is rated on a 6-point Likert scale ranging from 1 (almost always) to 6 (almost never) ( Brown and Ryan, 2003 ). All of these items were averaged as the MAAS score, with greater scores indicating higher levels of mindfulness (e.g., “I could be experiencing some emotion and not be conscious of it until sometime later”). The Chinese version of MAAS has been developed as a reliable and valid instrument to assess trait levels of mindfulness with adequate model fit for confirmatory factor analysis as follows: χ 2 / df = 2.69, CFI = 0.94, non-normed fit index (NNFI) = 0.93, and RMSEA = 0.079 ( Deng et al., 2012 ). Cronbach’s alpha for the MAAS was 0.85, indicating good reliability.

Physical activity

The physical activity levels were gauged by the International Physical Activity Questionnaire Short Form (IPAQ), which assesses the time spent in different kinds of vigorous, and moderate physical activities, as well as walking and sedentary behaviors per week ( Craig et al., 2003 ). The IPAQ scoring protocol is to generate the total Metabolic Equivalent Task (MET) scores by multiplying the total minutes spent on vigorous, moderate physical activities, and walking by 8, 4, and 3.3, and then adding them together ( Craig et al., 2003 ). Finally, the total IPAQ scores were log-transformed so as to attain normal distribution. The Chinese version of IPAQ also had acceptable reliability with an intraclass correlation coefficient (ICC) of 0.79 ( Macfarlane et al., 2007 ).

The dispositional flow was assessed by the Short Dispositional Flow Scale (S-DFS) (Copyright © 2002, 2009 by S. A. Jackson, we have made a license purchase from Mind Garden, Inc., and received permission to use S-DFS in current study), which consists of 9 items and uses a 5-point Likert scale ranging from 1 (never) to 5 (always) ( Jackson et al., 2008 , 2010 ). The averaged scores for each item of S-DFS were calculated, with higher scores indicating greater levels of dispositional flow (e.g., “I found the experience extremely rewarding”). The validity on Chinese version of S-DFS has been examined with adequate model fit for confirmatory factor analysis as follows: χ 2 / df = 2.49, CFI = 0.91, NNFI = 0.88, and RMSEA = 0.058 ( Liu, 2010 ). Cronbach’s alpha for the S-DFS was 0.73, indicating satisfactory reliability.

Data analytic plan

Descriptive statistics and correlation analysis were conducted in SPSS. Multiple mediation analysis was performed in The PROCESS macro for SPSS, which was used to examine the multiple mediation model (model 4) ( Hayes, 2017 ). Model 4 is a multiple mediator models, whose mediators are allowed to be operated in parallel. In this study, physical activity (M1) and mindfulness (M2), which were assumed to be the mediators in parallel, were proposed to mediate the relationship between mind-wandering (X) and flow (Y). Since the bias-corrected bootstrap has been demonstrated to generate the most accurate confidence intervals in prior studies ( MacKinnon et al., 2004 ; Cheung and Lau, 2008 ), the present study would apply the boot-strapping method to determine the significance of mediation effects. And 5,000 bootstrap samples were employed to generate 95% bias-corrected CIs for the indirect effects, which indicate significant if zero does not fall within the CI.

Descriptive statistics and correlation analysis

Table 1 presents the means and results of bivariate correlation analysis, which indicated that the associations between wandering mind, physical activity, mindfulness, and flow were significant in the expected directions, except that there was not any association between physical activity and mindfulness. Change in mind-wandering was significantly and inversely associated with the change in physical activity, mindfulness, and flow. Change in flow was also strongly and positively related to change in physical activity and mindfulness. In addition, there was no significant correlation between age and other variables.

Descriptive statistics among key study variables ( n = 429).

# Physical activity logarithmic transformed. * p < 0.05; ** p < 0.01; *** p < 0.001.

According to Csikszentmihalyi’s (1997) research, human beings can experience flow when performing almost any activity. In the current study, we classified and counted types of different activities based on what the participants filled in S-DFS. Except for four people who did not fill in the relevant activity content, the rest of the subjects reported dispositional flow experience when attending the following specific activities: 84.62% of subjects reported participating in physical exercises (namely, ball sports, track-and-field, swimming, gymnastics, fitness, and martial arts), 9.32% of them reported taking part in leisure and entertainment activities (namely, watching videos, playing games, listening to music, drawing, and chatting), 4.66% of them reported engaging in learning, and 0.47% of them reported participating in maintenance activities (namely, eating and driving).

Multiple mediation analysis

The PROCESS macro for SPSS (model 4) was applied to examine the multiple mediation model. Model 4 is the multiple mediator model, whose mediators are assumed to arrange in parallel ( Hayes, 2017 ). In the current study, we used multiple mediation analysis (model 4) to test whether physical activity and mindfulness had any significant mediation effects on the relationship between mind-wandering and flow. In this study, the supposed order of independent, mediator, and dependent variables were mind-wandering (independent variable) predicted physical activity or mindfulness (two multiple mediators), which predicted flow (dependent variable). Since the bias-corrected bootstrap has shown to generate the most accurate CIs in prior studies ( MacKinnon et al., 2004 ; Cheung and Lau, 2008 ), such bootstrapping method was conducted to determine the significant mediation effects. And 5,000 bootstrap samples were applied to generate 95% bias-corrected CIs for the indirect effects, which indicate significant if zero do not fall within the CI.

Figure 1 and Table 2 present the multiple mediation model predicting flow in all the sample. Mind-wandering showed significant direct paths to the two mediators: physical activity ( a 1 = −0.053, p < 0.01) and mindfulness ( a 2 = −0.375, p < 0.001). Both mediated variables, physical activity ( b 1 = 0.243, p < 0.01) and mindfulness ( b 2 = 0.139, p < 0.01), revealed significant direct paths to flow. After controlling for the potential mediators of physical activity and mindfulness, mind-wandering showed no significant direct path to flow ( c ′ = −0.008, p = 0.817). The total effects of mind-wandering on flow were obtained by the sum of the direct and indirect effects: ( c = c ′ + a 1 b 1 + a 2 b 2 = −0.073, p < 0.05).

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is fpsyg-13-674501-g001.jpg

Mediational model of physical activity, mindfulness on mind-wandering and flow. * p < 0.05; ** p < 0.01; *** p < 0.001.

Regression coefficients, standard errors, and model summary information for the parallel multiple mediator model depicted in Figure 1 .

MW, Mind-wandering; PA, Physical activity; M, Mindfulness; F, Flow; Coeff., Coefficient; SE, Standard error.

Table 3 shows the indirect effects and the related 95% CIs. In one pathway of “ Mind-wandering➔Physical activity➔Flow ,” this indirect effect (−0.0128) with a 95% bootstrap CI of −0.0283 to −0.0039 was significant. Another pathway of “ Mind-wandering➔Mindfulness➔Flow ,” whose indirect effect (−0.0522) with a 95% bootstrap confidence interval of −0.0881 to −0.0185 was significant. The total indirect effect [−0.0650 = (−0.0128) + (−0.0522)] was also significant with a 95% bootstrap CI of −0.1018 to −0.0302. Based on all these results, it showed the link between mind-wandering and flow was significantly mediated by physical activity and mindfulness.

Indirect effects and 95% CIs.

*Empirical 95% CI does not overlap with zero. IndEff, Indirect effect.

In addition, effect contrasts (see Table 3 ) demonstrated that there was a significant difference in the two mediation effects between the indirect effects through physical activity and mindfulness [0.0394 = (−0.0128) to (−0.0522)], with a 95% bootstrap CI of 0.0025 to 0.0770. This indicated that mindfulness played a more important role than physical activity in the relationship between wandering-mind and flow.

The current study showed that physical activity and mindfulness significantly mediated the relationship between mind-wandering and flow, supporting the study hypothesis. Levels of mind-wandering correlated negatively with those of physical activity, mindfulness, and changes in flow correlated positively with changes in physical activity and mindfulness.

The negative correlation observed between mind-wandering and flow is consistent with previous findings, suggesting that these constructs can be viewed as opposites ( Marty-Dugas and Smilek, 2018 ; Lambert and Csikszentmihalyi, 2019 ) and supporting the greater likelihood of individuals with fewer spontaneous thoughts to experience flow and address current tasks.

As mentioned previously, mind-wandering and flow have been reported to be closely correlated to creativity, respectively ( MacDonald et al., 2006 ; Schooler et al., 2014 ; Williams et al., 2018 ; Schutte and Malouff, 2020 ), and our findings further confirmed that mind-wandering had a negative association with the flow. Further research is needed to examine the role of creativity in this relationship. Specifically, the identification of the types of spontaneous thought that facilitate and hinder the flow experience and creativity and the exploration of whether the flow is a mediator or a moderator of the relationship between mind-wandering and creativity, would be valuable.

As expected, mind-wandering predicted flow through the partial mediating effect of physical activity in this study. Nearly 85% of the participants in this study were engaged in physical exercise, related closely to the larger proportions of participants with sports- and physical education-focused majors. These results are consistent with previous reports of flow experiences mainly in the context of physical exercise ( Jackson et al., 2008 ; Liu, 2010 ), and with the associated nature of increases in these two variables. Contrary to the present findings, mind-wandering was associated positively with moderate-to-vigorous physical activity in another study ( Fanning et al., 2016 ); this difference may be due to differences in the measurement of mind-wandering and physical activity (a “Yes/No” question and accelerometers vs. the reliable and valid scales used in the current study). In future research, these tools should be applied concurrently to further clarify the relationship between mind-wandering and physical activity.

Notably, participants in this study reported experiencing flow not only during physical activity but also during engagement in leisure and entertainment activities, learning and maintenance activities (namely, eating and driving). Although individuals with flow experience feel in control and are deep enjoyment in their activities, such optimal experience is relatively rare in daily life ( Csikszentmihalyi, 1997 ; Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ). In most cases, an endless train of thought would stream through our mind, and be pervasive in our daily life ( Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). We have reported the negative association between mind-wandering and flow, and physical activity and mindfulness might be the mechanism between mind-wandering and flow. The findings provide good insight into how daily spontaneous thought may affect the flow, which may improve the quality of life, and offer additional evidence to support the Context Regulation Hypothesis on mind-wandering ( Smallwood and Andrews-Hanna, 2013 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ; Thomson et al., 2015 ; Smallwood et al., 2021 ).

Our findings further extend existing research by reporting the mediated effect of physical activity between mind-wandering and flow. People experiencing less mind-wandering are more likely to have higher levels of physical activity, enabling greater concentration on the information at hand, thereby bringing about more flow. More physically active people have been found to exhibit more satisfactory self-regulation ( Buckley et al., 2014 ; Fanning et al., 2017 ), which enables them to more flexibly allocate executive and attentive resources and gain more sense of control over their thoughts, emotions, and behaviors. Our results are consistent with these findings. Moreover, physical activity as exercise breaks could induce less mind-wandering and enhance learning performance ( Fenesi et al., 2018 ), suggesting that it facilitates the transformation of self-generated thoughts into goal-dependent processing and behavior. As mentioned previously, the spontaneous internal thoughts are dynamic, and mind-wandering is revealed as the adaptive attentional control to adjust the external environment ( Schooler et al., 2011 ; Kam et al., 2013 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). Our findings farther indicate that less mind-wandering might be related to have more attentional resources available to invest in the activity at hand and experience flow. And physical activity, as a beneficial means for promote attentional control and self-regulation, might be an important mechanism between mind-wandering and flow.

Our finding that mindfulness mediates the relationship between mind-wandering and flow is in line with previous studies that reported significant associations between mindfulness and wandering mind ( Mrazek et al., 2012 ; Stawarczyk et al., 2012 ), and flow ( Marty-Dugas and Smilek, 2018 ; Lambert and Csikszentmihalyi, 2019 ). Our participants’ MWQ scores reflect the detrimental aspects of mind-wandering, namely, interference with task execution. Mindfulness is an optimal strategy for the flexible regulation of attention ( Mrazek et al., 2012 ; Stawarczyk et al., 2012 ) and the awareness of external and internal stimuli to modulate mind-wandering ( Levinson et al., 2014 ; Schooler et al., 2014 ). As the task at hand progresses smoothly and attention resources are occupied by the relevant tasks, flow experience can be achieved through increased moment-to-moment attention ( Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ). On the other hand, self-generated thoughts about physical activity have been found to be related to more frequent participation in such activity, and thus constitute a positive form of mind-wandering that might stimulate physical activity ( Rice and Fredrickson, 2017 ). And as mentioned earlier, successful self-regulatory physical activity could enhance executive functions, and contribute to flow experience ( Jackson and Eklund, 2002 ; Elbe et al., 2010 ; Fanning et al., 2016 ). Thus, physical activity and mindfulness may both be influenced by spontaneous thoughts, and intervention involving them could be developed as strategies for thought regulation, and the promotion of concentration on the present moment, perhaps enabling the attainment of flow.

Limitations and future implications

When interpreting the contributions of the current findings, the limitations and future implications of this study should be considered. First, the generalizability of the current findings is limited by the sample composition; the majority of the participating college students were majoring in fields involving motor learning and sports training, and thus might have higher physical activity levels and more flow experience than observed in general populations. In future studies, the current mediation models should be tested with samples of college students whose majors are less associated with physical activity. Second, the parallel multiple mediator model used in this study was established in an Eastern cultural context; its validity in other counties and cultural contexts should be examined. Third, the cross-sectional correlational design of the study prevented us from inferring causality. In future research, physical activity and mindfulness interventions should be developed based on the present findings, and their effects on the relationship between mind-wandering and flow should be examined longitudinally. Fourth, the roles of factors such as age, gender, and personality traits in the mediating effects observed in this study need to be investigated. Fifth, the MAAS provides a one-dimensional measure of mindfulness. Other scales, such as the Five Facet Mindfulness Questionnaire (FFMQ), could be used to assess different aspects of mindfulness (e.g., observing, describing, acting with awareness, non-judgment, and non-reaction) ( Baer et al., 2006 ) and their impacts on the relationship with mind-wandering. Sixth, the scales used in the current study inevitably limited the reliability of our findings. In future research, the Experience Sampling Method should be used to dynamically assess mind-wandering, mindfulness, and flow in daily life, to confirm the findings obtained with the mediation models ( Nakamura and Csikszentmihalyi, 2014 ; Smallwood and Schooler, 2015 ). Finally, although we found no significant relationship between dispositional mindfulness and physical activity, the two mediators identified in this study, a positive association between state mindfulness and physical activity was observed in a previous study in which the State Mindfulness Scale for Physical Activity was developed ( Cox et al., 2016 ). Future studies should consider this issue with the application of this scale ( Cox et al., 2016 ).

The present study was aimed to investigate the relationships between mind-wandering, flow, physical activity, and mindfulness. We found a negative association between mind-wandering and flow, and the relationship was mediated by physical activity and mindfulness. The findings of this study have several practical implications. For instance, if individuals want to cultivate the flow in their daily life, they first need to decrease mind-wandering. Also, it raises the possibility that the development of physical activity and mindfulness can act as the preventive strategies to achieve flow.

Author’s note

The authors received a license to use the Short Dispositional Flow Scale (S-DFS) (Copyright © 2002, 2009, S. A. Jackson) from Mind Garden, Inc. and received permission to use S-DFS in the current study.

Data availability statement

Ethics statement.

The studies involving human participants were reviewed and approved by the Shanghai University of Sport, Shanghai, China; and Institute of Sports Science, Nantong University, Nantong, Jiangsu Province, China. The patients/participants provided their written informed consent to participate in this study.

Author contributions

All authors listed have made a substantial, direct, and intellectual contribution to the work, and approved it for publication.

This work was supported by the Humanities and Social Sciences Youth Foundation of Ministry of Education of China (Grant no. 20YJC890004), the China Postdoctoral Science Foundation Funded Project (Grant no. 2017M610266), and the Doctoral Science and Research of Nantong University (Grant no. 135419619002).

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Publisher’s note

All claims expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not necessarily represent those of their affiliated organizations, or those of the publisher, the editors and the reviewers. Any product that may be evaluated in this article, or claim that may be made by its manufacturer, is not guaranteed or endorsed by the publisher.

  • Baer R. A., Smith G. T., Hopkins J., Krietemeyer J., Toney L. (2006). Using self-report assessment methods to explore facets of mindfulness. Assessment 13 27–45. 10.1177/1073191105283504 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Brown K. W., Ryan R. M. (2003). The benefits of being present: mindfulness and its role in psychological well-being. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 84 822–848. 10.1037/0022-3514.84.4.822 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Buckley J., Cohen J. D., Kramer A. F., Mcauley E., Mullen S. P. (2014). Cognitive control in the self-regulation of physical activity and sedentary behavior. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8 :747. 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00747 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Burdett B. R. D., Charlton S. G., Starkey N. J. (2016). Not all minds wander equally: the influence of traits, states and road environment factors on self-reported mind-wandering during everyday driving. Accid. Anal. Prev. 95 1–7. 10.1016/j.aap.2016.06.012 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Cheung G. W., Lau R. S. (2008). Testing mediation and suppression effects of latent variables: bootstrapping with structural equation models. Organ. Res. Methods 11 296–325. 10.1177/1094428107300343 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Cox A. E., Ullrich-French S., French B. F. (2016). Validity evidence for the state mindfulness scale for physical activity. Meas. Phys. Educ. Exerc. Sci. 20 38–49. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Craig C. L., Marshall A. L., Sjöström M., Bauman A. E., Booth M. L., Ainsworth B. E., et al. (2003). International physical activity questionnaire: 12-country reliability and validity. Med. Sci. Sports Exerc. 35 1381–1395. 10.1249/01.MSS.0000078924.61453.FB [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Csikszentmihalyi M. (1997). Finding ?ow. New York, NY: Harper Collins. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dane E. (2011). Paying attention to mindfulness and its effects on task performance in the workplace. J. Manag. 37 997–1018. 10.1177/0149206310367948 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Decloe M. D., Kaczynski A. T., Havitz M. E. (2009). Social participation, flow and situational involvement in recreational physical activity. J. Leis. Res. 41 73–90. 10.1080/00222216.2009.11950160 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Deng Y. Q., Li S., Tang Y. Y. (2014). The relationship between wandering mind, depression and mindfulness. Mindfulness 5 124–128. 10.1007/s12671-012-0157-7 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Deng Y. Q., Li S., Tang Y. Y., Zhu L. H., Ryan R., Brown K. (2012). Psychometric properties of the Chinese translation of the mindful attention awareness scale (MAAS). Mindfulness 3 10–14. 10.1007/s12671-011-0074-1 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Deng Y., Zhang B., Zheng X., Liu Y., Wang X., Zhou C. (2019). The role of mindfulness and self-control in the relationship between mind-wandering and metacognition. Pers. Individ. Differ. 141 51–56. 10.1016/j.paid.2018.12.020 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Dust S. B. (2015). Mindfulness, flow, and mind wandering: the role of trait-based mindfulness in state-task alignment. Ind. Organ. Psychol. 8 609–614. 10.1017/iop.2015.87 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Elbe A. M., Strahler K., Krustrup P., Wikman J., Stelter R. (2010). Experiencing flow in different types of physical activity intervention programs: three randomized studies. Scand. J. Med. Sci. Sports 20 ( Suppl. 1 ) 111–117. 10.1111/j.1600-0838.2010.01112.x [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fanning J., Mackenzie M., Roberts S., Crato I., Ehlers D., Mcauley E. (2016). Physical activity, mind wandering, affect, and sleep: an ecological momentary assessment. JMIR Mhealth and Uhealth 4 :e104. 10.2196/mhealth.5855 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fanning J., Porter G., Awick E. A., Ehlers D. K., Roberts S. A., Cooke G., et al. (2017). Replacing sedentary time with sleep, light, or moderate-to-vigorous physical activity: effects on self-regulation and executive functioning. J. Behav. Med. 40 332–342. 10.1007/s10865-016-9788-9 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fenesi B., Lucibello K., Kim J. A., Heisz J. J. (2018). Sweat so you don’t forget: exercise breaks during a university lecture increase on-task attention and learning. J. Appl. Res. Mem. Cogn. 7 261–269. 10.1016/j.jarmac.2018.01.012 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Fortier M. S., Morgan T. L. (2021). How optimism and physical activity interplay to promote happiness. Curr. Psychol. 10.1007/s12144-020-01294-y [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Harris D. J., Vine S. J., Wilson M. R. (2017). “ Chapter 12 - Neurocognitive mechanisms of the flow state ,” in Progress in Brain Research , Vol. 234 eds Wilson M. R., Walsh V., Parkin B. (Amsterdam: Elsevier; ), 221–243. 10.1016/bs.pbr.2017.06.012 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Hayes A. F. (2017). Introduction to Mediation, Moderation, and Conditional Process Analysis: A Regression-Based Approach , 2nd Edn. New York, NY: Guilford Press. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Jackson S. A., Eklund R. C. (2002). Assessing flow in physical activity: the flow state scale–2 and dispositional flow scale–2. J. Sport Exerc. Psychol. 24 133–150. 10.1123/jsep.24.2.133 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Jackson S. A., Martin A. J., Eklund R. C. (2008). Long and short measures of flow: the construct validity of the FSS-2, DFS-2, and new brief counterparts. J. Sport Exerc. Psychol. 30 561–587. 10.1123/jsep.30.5.561 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Jackson S. A., Martin A. J., Eklund R. C. (2010). Short Dispositional Flow Scale. Menlo Park, CA: Mind Garden. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Ju Y., Lien Y. (2018). Who is prone to wander and when? Examining an integrative effect of working memory capacity and mindfulness trait on mind-wandering under different task loads. Conscious. Cogn. 63 1–10. 10.1016/j.concog.2018.06.006 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Kam J. W., Dao E., Stanciulescu M., Tildesley H. (2013). Mind wandering and the adaptive control of attentional resources. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 25 952–960. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Karunamuni N., Weerasekera R. (2019). Theoretical foundations to guide mindfulness meditation: a path to wisdom. Curr. Psychol. 38 627–646. 10.1007/s12144-017-9631-7 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Lambert J., Csikszentmihalyi M. (2019). Facilitating or foiling flow: the role of momentary perceptions of feedback. J. Posit. Psychol. 15 208–219. 10.1080/17439760.2019.1578893 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Levinson D. B., Stoll E. L., Kindy S. D., Merry H. L., Davidson R. J. (2014). A mind you can count on: validating breath counting as a behavioral measure of mindfulness. Front. Psychol. 5 :1202. 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01202 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Liu W. (2010). Revision on Chinese edition of the short flow state scale and the short dispositional flow scale. China Sport Sci. 30 64–70. 10.16469/j.css.2010.12.012 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Luo Y., Zhu R., Ju E., You X. (2016). Validation of the Chinese version of the mind-wandering questionnaire (MWQ) and the mediating role of self-esteem in the relationship between mind-wandering and life satisfaction for adolescents. Pers. Individ. Differ. 92 118–122. 10.1016/j.paid.2015.12.028 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • MacDonald R., Byrne C., Carlton L. (2006). Creativity and flow in musical composition: an empirical investigation. Psychol. Music 34 292–306. 10.1177/0305735606064838 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Macfarlane D. J., Lee C. C. Y., Ho E. Y. K., Chan K. L., Chan D. T. S. (2007). Reliability and validity of the Chinese version of IPAQ (short, last 7 days). J. Sci. Med. Sport 10 45–51. 10.1016/j.jsams.2006.05.003 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • MacKinnon D. P., Lockwood C. M., Williams J. (2004). Con?dence limits for the indirect effect: distribution of the product and resampling methods. Multivariate Behav. Res. 39 99–128. 10.1207/s15327906mbr3901_4 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Marty-Dugas J., Smilek D. (2018). Deep, effortless concentration: re-examining the flow concept and exploring relations with inattention, absorption, and personality. Psychol. Res. 83 1760–1777. 10.1007/s00426-018-1031-6 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mooneyham B. W., Schooler J. W. (2013). The costs and benefits of mind-wandering: a review. Can. J. Exp. Psychol. 67 11–18. 10.1037/a0031569 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mrazek M. D., Phillips D. T., Franklin M. S., Broadway J. M., Schooler J. W. (2013). Young and restless: validation of the mind-wandering questionnaire (MWQ) reveals disruptive impact of mind-wandering for youth. Front. Psychol. 4 :560. 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00560 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Mrazek M. D., Smallwood J., Schooler J. W. (2012). Mindfulness and mind-wandering: finding convergence through opposing constructs. Emotion 12 442–448. 10.1037/a0026678 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Nakamura J., Csikszentmihalyi M. (2014). “ The concept of flow ,” in Flow and the Foundations of Positive Psychology: The Collected Works of Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi , ed. Csikszentmihalyi M. (Amsterdam: Springer; ), 239–263. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Plante T. G., Rodin J. (1990). Physical fitness and enhanced psychological health. Curr. Psychol. 9 3–24. 10.1007/BF02686764 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Prakash R. S., Fountain-Zaragoza S., Kramer A. F., Samimy S., Wegman J. (2020). Mindfulness and attention: current state-of-affairs and future considerations. J. Cogn. Enhance. 4 340–367. 10.1007/s41465-019-00144-5 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Rice E. L., Fredrickson B. L. (2017). Of passions and positive spontaneous thoughts. Cogn. Ther. Res. 41 350–361. 10.1007/s10608-016-9755-3 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Schooler J. W., Mrazek M. D., Franklin M. S., Baird B., Mooneyham B. W., Zedelius C., et al. (2014). “ Chapter One - The middle way: finding the balance between mindfulness and mind-wandering ,” in Psychology of Learning and Motivation , Vol. 60 ed. Ross B. H. (Cambridge, MA: Academic Press; ), 1–33. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Schooler J. W., Smallwood J., Christoff K., Handy T. C., Reichle E. D., Sayette M. A. (2011). Meta-awareness, perceptual decoupling and the wandering mind. Trends Cogn. Sci. 15 319–326. 10.1016/j.tics.2011.05.006 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Schutte N. S., Malouff J. M. (2020). Connections between curiosity, flow and creativity. Pers. Individ. Differ. 152 :109555. 10.1016/j.paid.2019.109555 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Šimleša M., Guegan J., Blanchard E., Tarpin-Bernard F., Buisine S. (2018). The flow engine framework: a cognitive model of optimal human experience. Eur. J. Psychol. 14 232–253. 10.5964/ejop.v14i1.1370 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Smallwood J., Andrews-Hanna J. (2013). Not all minds that wander are lost: the importance of a balanced perspective on the mind-wandering state. Front. Psychol. 4 :441. 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00441 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Smallwood J., Schooler J. W. (2015). The science of mind wandering: empirically navigating the stream of consciousness. Ann. Rev. Psychol. 66 487–518. 10.1146/annurev-psych-010814-015331 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Smallwood J., Turnbull A., Wang H., Ho N. S. P., Poerio G. L., Karapanagiotidis T., et al. (2021). The neural correlates of ongoing conscious thought. iScience 24 :102132. 10.1016/j.isci.2021.102132 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Stavrou N. A. M., Psychountaki M., Georgiadis E., Karteroliotis K., Zervas Y. (2015). Flow theory - goal orientation theory: positive experience is related to athlete’s goal orientation. Front. Psychol. 6 :1499. 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01499 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Stawarczyk D., Majerus S., Der Linden M. V., Dargembeau A. (2012). Using the daydreaming frequency scale to investigate the relationships between mind-wandering, psychological well-being, and present-moment awareness. Front. Psychol. 3 :363. 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00363 [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Thomson D. R., Ralph B. C. W., Besner D., Smilek D. (2015). The more your mind wanders, the smaller your attentional blink: an individual differences study. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 68 181–191. 10.1080/17470218.2014.940985 [ PubMed ] [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Williams K. J. H., Lee K. E., Hartig T., Sargent L. D., Williams N. S. G., Johnson K. A. (2018). Conceptualising creativity benefits of nature experience: attention restoration and mind wandering as complementary processes. J. Environ. Psychol. 59 36–45. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Winneke A., Godde B., Reuter E., Vieluf S., Voelcker-Rehage C. (2012). The association between physical activity and attentional control in younger and older middle-aged adults. GeroPsych J. Gerontopsychol. Geriatr. Psychiatry 25 207–221. [ Google Scholar ]
  • Wright J., Sadlo G., Stew G. (2006). Challenge-skills and mindfulness: an exploration of the conundrum of flow process. OTJR: Occup. Particip. Health 26 25–32. 10.1177/153944920602600104 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Xie L. (2021). Flow in work teams: the role of emotional regulation, voice, and team mindfulness. Curr. Psychol. 10.1007/s12144-020-01179-0 [ CrossRef ] [ Google Scholar ]
  • Zedelius C. M., Schooler J. W. (2020). “ Chapter 3 - Capturing the dynamics of creative daydreaming ,” in Creativity and the Wandering Mind , eds Preiss D. D., Cosmelli D., Kaufman J. C. (Cambridge, MA: Academic Press; ), 55–72. [ Google Scholar ]

VIDEO

  1. wandering wanderland

  2. GMS & Volcano On Mars

  3. wandering wanderland

  4. Walter Wanderley

  5. Mind Wandering

  6. MIND-WANDERING

COMMENTS

  1. Mind-wandering

    Il mind-wandering (in italiano reso anche con mente vagabonda) è latamente definito come pensieri che non scaturiscono dal compito presente. Il ... Questo significa che una funzione esecutiva di aggiornamento a basse prestazioni può essere un indicatore di alto mind-wandering. La memoria di lavoro fa affidamento sulle funzioni esecutive, e il ...

  2. Mind-wandering

    Mind-wandering. Mind-wandering is loosely defined as thoughts that are not produced from the current task. Mind-wandering consists of thoughts that are task-unrelated and stimulus-independent. [1] [2] This can be in the form of three different subtypes: positive constructive daydreaming, guilty fear of failure, and poor attentional control.

  3. Una mente errante: il fenomeno del mind-wandering

    Il fenomeno del mind-wandering indica la tendenza della mente a vagare e a spostare l'attenzione su altro e questo ha dei costi ma anche vantaggi. Il tuo browser non supporta il tag video. Il mind-wandering riflette dunque la nostra tendenza e capacità a sganciare l'attenzione dalla percezione senza un'intenzione chiaramente definita; tale ...

  4. Why does the mind wander?

    Introduction Minds wander. Some wander more than others, but human ones wander a lot. A much-cited estimate, due to Killingsworth and Gilbert (2010), has it that the awake human mind spends from a third to half its time wandering.That's a big range, a rough estimate, and there are good reasons to be suspicious of it (see Seli et al. 2018).The actual number will likely depend a bit upon the ...

  5. Why Do Our Minds Wander?

    A scientist says mind-wandering or daydreaming help prepare us for the future. Scientists are beginning to understand when and why minds start to wander. Knowable Magazine. When psychologist ...

  6. Mind Wandering

    Mind Wandering and Other Lapses. J. Smallwood, in Encyclopedia of Consciousness, 2009 Mind wandering is a universal human experience in which the focus of attention temporarily shifts from what we are doing. This article describes how to conceptualize these shifts in attention as changes in the flow of information through an attentional system and considers the different explanations offered ...

  7. (PDF) Mind Wandering: una mente vagabonda

    Abstract. Il fenomeno del mind-wandering indica la tendenza della mente a vagare e a spostare l'attenzione su altro e questo ha dei costi ma anche dei vantaggi. Il mind-wandering riflette la ...

  8. The brain on silent: mind wandering, mindful awareness, and states of

    Abstract. Mind wandering and mindfulness are often described as divergent mental states with opposing effects on cognitive performance and mental health. Spontaneous mind wandering is typically associated with self-reflective states that contribute to negative processing of the past, worrying/fantasizing about the future, and disruption of ...

  9. Mind-wandering as spontaneous thought: a dynamic framework

    In the past 15 years, mind-wandering and spontaneous thought have become prominent topics in cognitive psychology and neuroscience 2. However, most theories of mind-wandering still overlook the ...

  10. The Wandering Mind: How the Brain Allows Us to Mentally Wander Off to

    A unique human characteristic is our ability to mind wander—these are periods of time when our attention drifts away from the task-at-hand to focus on thoughts that are unrelated to the task. Mind wandering has some benefits, such as increased creativity, but it also has some negative consequences, such as mistakes in the task we are supposed to be performing.

  11. How to Tame Your Wandering Mind

    Find counselling to help with ADHD. The first step to mastering mind-wandering is to plan time for it. Use a schedule maker and block off time in your day to let your thoughts flow freely. You ...

  12. 8 The Philosophy of Mind-Wandering

    We begin by criticizing the standard definitions of mind-wandering in psychology, according to which mind-wandering is "task-unrelated thought" or "stimulus-independent thought" (see Irving, 2016).Scientists have used these definitions to produce important findings and bring mind-wandering into center stage in psychology and cognitive neuroscience (Schooler, Smallwood, Christoff, Handy ...

  13. Mind wandering and stress: When you don't like the present moment

    Mind wandering vs. engagement in the moment are frequent states of mind that may offer important clues or even serve as determinants of one's daily mental health and happiness. The findings presented here provide the first empirical evidence that experiencing psychological stress shapes these mind states at the daily level. We found that ...

  14. It's normal for your mind to wander. Here's how to maximise the benefits

    Mind wandering is believed to play an important role in generating new ideas, conclusions or insights (also known as "aha! moments"). This is because it can give your mind a break and free it ...

  15. How to Focus a Wandering Mind

    Ironically, mind-wandering itself can help strengthen our ability to focus, if leveraged properly. This can be achieved using an age-old skill: meditation. Indeed, a new wave of research reveals what happens in our brains when our minds wander—and sheds light on the host of cognitive and emotional benefits that come with increased focus.

  16. The impacts of mind-wandering on flow: Examining the critical role of

    Thus, mind-wandering might be expected to predict flow, but more research is needed to examine this potential relationship and its mediators. Mind-wandering occurs with high frequency, occupying about half of the individuals' waking hours, and is thus, a prevalent and important experience in daily life (Smallwood and Schooler, 2015).

  17. How to tame a wandering mind: 12 ways to refocus your mind

    Physical activity, like a short walk or shaking out your arms and legs in between meetings, can interrupt the cycle of mind wandering and re-energize your focus. 💙 If the mind is wandering, try bringing it back to the present moment through movement. Check out Mindful Movement with Mel Mah. 7. Use grounding exercises.

  18. Let It Go: The Benefits of Mind Wandering

    In other words, participants who were given a task that encouraged mind wandering were able to come up with more unique uses for items than in other conditions - including the Rest condition (1). It should be noted that this improvement was only in the repeated items, supporting the idea that mind wandering allowed participants to mull over and ...

  19. Why Mind Wandering Can Be So Miserable, According to Happiness Experts

    In the last 15 years, the science of mind wandering has mushroomed as a topic of scholarly study, thanks in part to advances in brain imaging. But for a long time, it was still difficult to see ...

  20. A Moscow state of mind

    A Moscow state of mind. Moscow is a city of many facets but, to all who visit, the iconic domes of St. Basil's Cathedral and majestic sweep of Red Square do add up to a bewitching mix of ...

  21. 23 Things to Do in Moscow, Russia

    In the morning hours, stumble upon yoga classes and dance lessons before joggers and cyclists arrive in equal numbers. If you have time, get about on foot to appreciate the manicured gardens along the walking path that guides you to Sparrow Hill. From the top, you can bask in exquisite views of the Moscow skyline.

  22. [Full Version] Walking Streets Moscow. Wandering ...

    Wandering around the Moscow city center. New Arbat Ave, Old Arbat, Vozdvizhenka Street. Summer in Russia. June 13, 2022Support Channel BinanceID 436130624USD...

  23. [Full Version] Walking Streets Moscow. Wandering ...

    Walking around Moscow city center. June 10, 2022Support Channel BinanceID 436130624USDT (TRC20) TDwYeKQbdm9NXpgQAcC9gM9SPPPUvGy16BBTC bc1qhmuqq7wh4qt9xpvthew...